<SPAN name="toc109" id="toc109"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="pdf110" id="pdf110"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="Book_II_Chapter_VI" id="Book_II_Chapter_VI" class="tei tei-anchor"></SPAN>
<h2><span>Chapter VI. Of Rent.</span></h2>
<SPAN name="toc111" id="toc111"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 1. Rent the Effect of a Natural Monopoly.</span></h3>
<p>
The requisites of production being labor, capital,
and natural agents, the only person, besides the laborer and
the capitalist, whose consent is necessary to production, and
who can claim a share of the produce as the price of that
consent, is the person who, by the arrangements of society,
possesses exclusive power over some natural agent. The
land is the principal of the natural agents which are capable
of being appropriated, and the consideration paid for its use
is called rent. Landed proprietors are the only class, of any
numbers or importance, who have a claim to a share in the
distribution of the produce, through their ownership of something
which neither they nor any one else have produced.
If there be any other cases of a similar nature, they will be
easily understood, when the nature and laws of rent are
comprehended.</p>
<p>
It is at once evident that rent is the effect of a monopoly.
The reason why land-owners are able to require rent
for their land is, that it is a commodity which many want,
and which no one can obtain but from them. If all the land
of the country belonged to one person, he could fix the rent
at his pleasure. This case, however, is nowhere known to
exist; and the only remaining supposition is that of free
competition; the land-owners being supposed to be, as in
fact they are, too numerous to combine.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
The ratio of the land to the cultivators shows the limited
quantity of land. It is very desirable to keep the connection
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
of one part of the subject with another wherever possible.
</span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Agricultural rent, as it actually exists,</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> says Mr.
Cairnes,</span><SPAN id="noteref_180" name="noteref_180" href="#note_180"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">180</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
truly, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">is not a consequence of the </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">monopoly</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> of the soil, but
of its diminishing productiveness.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> The doctrine of rent depends
upon the law of diminishing returns; and it is only by
the pressure of population upon land that the lessened productiveness
of land, whether because of poorer qualities or poorer
situations, is made apparent. Or, to take things in their natural
sequence, an increase of population necessitates more food;
and this implies a resort to more expensive methods, or poorer
soils, so soon as land is pushed to the extent that it will not
yield an increased crop for the same application of labor and
capital as formerly. Different qualities of land, then, being
in cultivation at the same time, the better qualities must, of
course, yield a greater return than the poorer, and the conditions
then exist under which land pays rent. Those, therefore,
who admit the law of diminishing returns are inevitably led to
the doctrine of rent.
</span>
<SPAN name="toc112" id="toc112"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 2. No Land can pay Rent except Land of such Quality or Situation as exists in less Quantity than the Demand.</span></h3>
<p>
A thing which is limited in quantity, even though
its possessors do not act in concert, is still a monopolized
article. But even when monopolized, a thing which is the
gift of nature, and requires no labor or outlay as the condition
of its existence, will, if there be competition among
the holders of it, command a price only if it exist in less
quantity than the demand.</p>
<p>
If the whole land of a country were required for cultivation,
all of it might yield a rent. But in no country of any
extent do the wants of the population require that all the
land, which is capable of cultivation, should be cultivated.
The food and other agricultural produce which the people
need, and which they are willing and able to pay for at a
price which remunerates the grower, may always be obtained
without cultivating all the land; sometimes without cultivating
more than a small part of it; the more fertile lands,
or those in the more convenient situations, being of course
preferred. There is always, therefore, some land which can
not, in existing circumstances, pay any rent; and no land
ever pays rent unless, in point of fertility or situation, it
belongs to those superior kinds which exist in less quantity
than the demand—which can not be made to yield all the
produce required for the community, unless on terms still
less advantageous than the resort to less favored soils. (1.)
The worst land which can be cultivated as a means of subsistence
is that which will just replace the seed and the food
of the laborers employed on it, together with what Dr. Chalmers
calls their secondaries; that is, the laborers required
for supplying them with tools, and with the remaining necessaries
of life. Whether any given land is capable of doing
more than this is not a question of political economy, but of
physical fact. The supposition leaves nothing for profits,
nor anything for the laborers except necessaries: the land,
therefore, can only be cultivated by the laborers themselves,
or else at a pecuniary loss; and, <span class="tei tei-foreign"><span style="font-style: italic">a fortiori</span></span>, can not in
any contingency afford a rent. (2.) The worst land which can be
cultivated as an investment for capital is that which, after
replacing the seed, not only feeds the agricultural laborers
and their secondaries, but affords them the current rate of
wages, which may extend to much more than mere necessaries,
and leaves, for those who have advanced the wages of
these two classes of laborers, a surplus equal to the profit
they could have expected from any other employment of
their capital. (3.) Whether any given land can do more than
this is not merely a physical question, but depends partly
on the market value of agricultural produce. What the
land can do for the laborers and for the capitalist, beyond
feeding all whom it directly or indirectly employs, of course
depends upon what the remainder of the produce can be
sold for. The higher the market value of produce, the
lower are the soils to which cultivation can descend, consistently
with affording to the capital employed the ordinary
rate of profit.</p>
<p>
As, however, differences of fertility slide into one another
by insensible gradations; and differences of accessibility,
that is, of distance from markets do the same; and
since there is land so barren that it could not pay for its
cultivation at any price; it is evident that, whatever the
price may be, there must in any extensive region be some
land which at that price will just pay the wages of the cultivators,
and yield to the capital employed the ordinary
profit, and no more. Until, therefore, the price rises higher,
or until some improvement raises that particular land to a
higher place in the scale of fertility, it can not pay any rent.
It is evident, however, that the community needs the produce
of this quality of land; since, if the lands more fertile
or better situated than it could have sufficed to supply the
wants of society, the price would not have risen so high as
to render its cultivation profitable. This land, therefore,
will be cultivated; and we may lay it down as a principle
that, so long as any of the land of a country which is fit for
cultivation, and not withheld from it by legal or other factitious
obstacles, is not cultivated, the worst land in actual
cultivation (in point of fertility and situation together) pays
no rent.</p>
<SPAN name="toc113" id="toc113"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 3. The Rent of Land is the Excess of its Return above the Return to the worst Land in Cultivation.</span></h3>
<p>
If, then, of the land in cultivation, the part which
yields least return to the labor and capital employed on it
gives only the ordinary profit of capital, without leaving
anything for rent, a standard [i.e., the <span class="tei tei-q">“margin of cultivation”</span>]
is afforded for estimating the amount of rent which
will be yielded by all other land. Any land yields just as
much more than the ordinary profits of stock as it yields
more than what is returned by the worst land in cultivation.
The surplus is what the farmer can afford to pay as rent to
the landlord; and since, if he did not so pay it, he would
receive more than the ordinary rate of profit, the competition
of other capitalists, that competition which equalizes
the profits of different capitals, will enable the landlord to
appropriate it. The rent, therefore, which any land will
yield, is the excess of its produce, beyond what would be
returned to the same capital if employed on the worst land
in cultivation.</p>
<p>
It has been denied that there can be any land in cultivation
which pays no rent, because landlords (it is contended)
would not allow their land to be occupied without payment.
Inferior land, however, does not usually occupy, without
interruption, many square miles of ground; it is dispersed
here and there, with patches of better land intermixed, and
the same person who rents the better land obtains along
with it the inferior soils which alternate with it. He pays
a rent, nominally for the whole farm, but calculated on the
produce of those parts alone (however small a portion of
the whole) which are capable of returning more than the
common rate of profit. It is thus scientifically true that
the remaining parts pay no rent.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
This point seems to need some illustration. Suppose that
all the lands in a community are of five different grades of
productiveness. When the price of agricultural produce was
such that grades one, two, and three all came into cultivation,
lands of poorer quality would not be cultivated. When a man
rents a farm, he always gets land of varying degrees of fertility
within its limits. Now, in determining what he ought to
pay as rent, the farmer will agree to give that which will still
leave him a profit on his working capital; if in his fields he
finds land which would not enter into the question of rental,
because it did not yield more than the profit on working it,
after he rented the farm he would find it to his interest to cultivate
it, simply because it yielded him a profit, and because
he was not obliged to pay rent upon it; if required to pay rent
for it, he would lose the ordinary rate of profit, would have no
reason for cultivating it, of course, and would throw it out of
cultivation. Moreover, suppose that lands down to grade three
paid rent when A took the farm; now, if the price of produce
rises slightly, grade four may pay something, but possibly not
enough to warrant any rent going to a landlord. A will put
capital on it for this return, but certainly not until the price
warrants it; that is, not until the price will return him at least
the cost of working the land, </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">plus</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> the profit on his outlay. But
the community needed this land, or the price would not have
gone up to the point which makes possible its cultivation even
for a profit, without rent. There must always be somewhere
some land affected in just this way.
</span>
<SPAN name="toc114" id="toc114"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 4. —Or to the Capital employed in the least advantageous Circumstances.</span></h3>
<p>
Let us, however, suppose that there were a validity
in this objection, which can by no means be conceded to it;
that, when the demand of the community had forced up food
to such a price as would remunerate the expense of producing
it from a certain quality of soil, it happened nevertheless
that all the soil of that quality was withheld from cultivation,
the increase of produce, which the wants of society required,
would for the time be obtained wholly (as it always is partially),
not by an extension of cultivation, but by an increased
application of labor and capital to land already cultivated.</p>
<p>
Now we have already seen that this increased application
of capital, other things being unaltered, is always attended
with a smaller proportional return. The rise of price enables
measures to be taken for increasing the produce, which could
not have been taken with profit at the previous price. The
farmer uses more expensive manures, or manures land which
he formerly left to nature; or procures lime or marl from a
distance, as a dressing for the soil; or pulverizes or weeds
it more thoroughly; or drains, irrigates, or subsoils portions
of it, which at former prices would not have paid the cost
of the operation; and so forth. The farmer or improver
will only consider whether the outlay he makes for the purpose
will be returned to him with the ordinary profit, and
not whether any surplus will remain for rent. Even, therefore,
if it were the fact that there is never any <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">land</span></em> taken
into cultivation, for which rent, and that too of an amount
worth taking into consideration, was not paid, it would be
true, nevertheless, that there is always some <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">agricultural
capital</span></em> which pays no rent, because it returns nothing beyond
the ordinary rate of profit: this capital being the portion
of capital last applied—that to which the last addition
to the produce was due; or (to express the essentials of the
case in one phrase) that which is applied in the least favorable
circumstances. But the same amount of demand and
the same price, which enable this least productive portion of
capital barely to replace itself with the ordinary profit, enable
every other portion to yield a surplus proportioned to
the advantage it possesses. And this surplus it is which
competition enables the landlord to appropriate.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
If land were all occupied, and of only one grade, the first
installment of labor and capital produced, we will say, twenty
bushels of wheat; when the price of wheat rose, and it became
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
profitable to resort to greater expense on the soil, a second installment
of the same amount of labor and capital when applied,
however, only yielded fifteen bushels more; a third, ten bushels
more; and a fourth, five bushels more. The soil now gives fifty
bushels only under the highest pressure. But, if it was profitable
to invest the same installment of labor and capital simply
for the five bushels that at first had received a return of twenty
bushels, the price must have gone up so that five bushels should
sell for as much as the twenty did formerly; so,
</span><span class="tei tei-foreign"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">mutatis mutandis</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">,
of installments second and third. So that if the demand
is such as to require all of the fifty bushels, the agricultural
capital which produced the five bushels will be the standard
according to which the rent of the capital, which grew twenty,
fifteen, and ten bushels respectively, is measured. The principle
is exactly the same as if equal installments of capital and
labor were invested on four different grades of land returning
twenty, fifteen, ten, and five bushels for each installment. Or,
as if in the table on </span><SPAN href="#Pg240" class="tei tei-ref"><span style="font-size: 90%">page 240</span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">, A, B, C, and D each represented
different installments of the same amount of labor and capital
put upon the same spot of ground, instead of being, as there,
put upon different grades of land.
</span>
<p>
The rent of all land is measured by the excess of the return
to the whole capital employed on it above what is necessary
to replace the capital with the ordinary rate of profit,
or, in other words, above what the same capital would yield
if it were all employed in as disadvantageous circumstances
as the least productive portion of it: whether that least productive
portion of capital is rendered so by being employed
on the worst soil, or by being expended in extorting more
produce from land which already yielded as much as it could
be made to part with on easier terms.</p>
<p>
It will be true that the farmer requires the ordinary rate
of profit on the whole of his capital; that whatever it returns
to him beyond this he is obliged to pay to the landlord, but
will not consent to pay more; that there is a portion of capital
applied to agriculture in such circumstances of productiveness
as to yield only the ordinary profits; and that the
difference between the produce of this and of any other capital
of similar amount is the measure of the tribute which that
other capital can and will pay, under the name of rent, to
the landlord. This constitutes a law of rent, as near the
truth as such a law can possibly be; though of course modified
or disturbed, in individual cases, by pending contracts,
individual miscalculations, the influence of habit, and even
the particular feelings and dispositions of the persons concerned.</p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
The law of rent, in the economic sense, operates in the
United States as truly as elsewhere, although there is no separate
class of landlords here. With us, almost all land is owned
by the cultivator; so that two functions, those of the landlord
and farmer, are both united in one person. Although one payment
is made, it is still just as distinctly made up of two parts,
one of which is a payment to the owner for the superior quality
of his soil, and the other a payment (to the same person, if the
owner is the cultivator) of profit on the farmer's working capital.
Land which in the United States will only return enough
to pay a profit on this capital can not pay any rent. And land
which can pay more than a profit on this working capital, returns
that excess as rent, even if the farmer is also the owner
and landlord. The principle which regulates the amount of
that excess—which is the essential point—is the principle which
determines the amount of economic rent, and it holds true in
the United States or Finland, provided only that different
grades of land are called into cultivation. The governing
principle is the same, no matter whether a payment is made to
one man as profit and to another as rent, or whether the two
payments are made to the same man in two capacities. It has
been urged that the law of rent does not hold in the United
States, because </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the price of grain and other agricultural produce
has not risen in proportion to the increase of our numbers,
as it ought to have done if Ricardo's theory were true, but has
fallen, since 1830, though since that time our population has
been more than tripled.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><SPAN id="noteref_181" name="noteref_181" href="#note_181"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">181</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> This overlooks the fact that we
have not even yet taken up all our best agricultural lands, so
that for some products the law of diminishing productiveness
has not yet shown itself. The reason is, that the extension of
our railway system has only of late years brought the really
good grain-lands into cultivation. The fact that there has been
no rise in agricultural products is due to the enormous extent of
marvelously fertile grain-lands in the West, and to the cheapness
of transportation from those districts to the seaboard.
</span></p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
For a general understanding of the law of rent the following
table will show how, under constant increase of population
(represented by four different advances of population, in the
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
first column), first the best and then the poorer lands are
brought into cultivation. We will suppose (1) that the most
fertile land, A, at first pays no rent; then (2), when more food
is wanted than land A can supply, it will be profitable to till
land B, but which, as yet, pays no rent. But if eighteen bushels
are a sufficient return to a given amount of labor and capital,
then when an equal amount of labor and capital engaged
on A returns twenty-four bushels, six of that are beyond the
ordinary profit, and form the rent on land A, and so on; C will
next be the line of comparison, and then D; as the poorer soils
are cultivated, the rent of A increases:
</span></p>
<table summary="This is a table" cellspacing="0" class="tei tei-table" style="margin-bottom: 1.00em"><colgroup span="9"></colgroup><tbody><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell">Population Increase.</td><td class="tei tei-cell">A</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">B</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td><td class="tei tei-cell">C</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td><td class="tei tei-cell">D</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell"></td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell"></td><td class="tei tei-cell">24 bushels</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">18 bushels</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td><td class="tei tei-cell">12 bushels</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">6 bushels</td><td class="tei tei-cell"></td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell"></td><td class="tei tei-cell">Total product</td><td class="tei tei-cell">Rent in Bushels</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">Total product</td><td class="tei tei-cell">Rent in Bushels</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">Total product</td><td class="tei tei-cell">Rent in Bushels</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">Total product</td><td class="tei tei-cell">Rent in Bushels</td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell">I.</td><td class="tei tei-cell">24</td><td class="tei tei-cell">0</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell">II.</td><td class="tei tei-cell">24</td><td class="tei tei-cell">6</td><td class="tei tei-cell">18</td><td class="tei tei-cell">0</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell">III.</td><td class="tei tei-cell">24</td><td class="tei tei-cell">12</td><td class="tei tei-cell">18</td><td class="tei tei-cell">6</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">12</td><td class="tei tei-cell">0</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td><td class="tei tei-cell">..</td></tr><tr class="tei tei-row"><td class="tei tei-cell">IV.</td><td class="tei tei-cell">24</td><td class="tei tei-cell">18</td><td class="tei tei-cell">18</td><td class="tei tei-cell">12</td>
<td class="tei tei-cell">12</td><td class="tei tei-cell">6</td><td class="tei tei-cell">6</td><td class="tei tei-cell">0</td></tr></tbody></table>
<SPAN name="toc115" id="toc115"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 5. Opposing Views of the Law of Rent.</span></h3>
<p>
Under the name of rent, many payments are commonly
included, which are not a remuneration for the original
powers of the land itself, but for capital expended on
it. The buildings are as distinct a thing from the farm as
the stock or the timber on it; and what is paid for them can
no more be called rent of land than a payment for cattle
would be, if it were the custom that the landlord should
stock the farm for the tenant. The buildings, like the cattle,
are not land, but capital, regularly consumed and reproduced;
and all payments made in consideration for them are properly
interest.</p>
<p>
But with regard to capital actually sunk in improvements,
and not requiring periodical renewal, but spent once for all
in giving the land a permanent increase of productiveness,
it appears to me that the return made to such capital loses
altogether the character of profits, and is governed by the
principles of rent. It is true that a landlord will not expend
capital in improving his estate unless he expects from the
improvement an increase of income surpassing the interest
of his outlay. Prospectively, this increase of income may
be regarded as profit; but, when the expense has been incurred
and the improvement made, the rent of the improved
land is governed by the same rules as that of the unimproved.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Mr. Carey (as well as Bastiat) has declared that there is a
law of increasing returns from land. He points out that everything
now existing could be reproduced to-day at a less cost
than that involved in its original production, owing to our
advance in skill, knowledge, and all the arts of production;
that, for example, it costs less to make an axe now than it did
five hundred years ago; so also with a farm, since a farm of a
given amount of productiveness can be brought into cultivation
at less cost to-day than that originally spent upon it.
The gain of society has, we all admit, been such that we produce
almost everything at a less cost now than long ago; but
to class a farm and an axe together overlooks, in the most
remarkable way, the fact that land can not be created by labor
and capital, while axes can, and that too indefinitely. Nor can
the </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">produce</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> from the land be increased indefinitely at a diminishing
cost. This is sometimes denied by the appeal to facts:
</span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">It can be abundantly proved that, if we take any two periods
sufficiently distant to afford a fair test, whether fifty or one
hundred or five hundred years, the production of the land
relatively to the labor employed upon it has progressively become
greater and greater.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><SPAN id="noteref_182" name="noteref_182" href="#note_182"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">182</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> But this does not prove that an
existing tendency to diminishing returns has not been more
than offset by the progress of the arts and improvements.
</span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">The advance of a ship against wind and tide is [no] proof
that there is no wind and tide.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span>
<p>
In a work entitled <span class="tei tei-q">“The Past, the Present, and the
Future,”</span> Mr. Carey takes [a] ground of objection to the
Ricardo theory of rent, namely, that in point of historical
fact the lands first brought under cultivation are not the
most fertile, but the barren lands. <span class="tei tei-q">“We find the settler invariably
occupying the high and thin lands requiring little
clearing and no drainage. With the growth of population
and wealth, other soils yielding a larger return to labor are
always brought into activity, with a constantly increasing
return to the labor expended upon them.”</span></p>
<p>
In whatever order the lands come into cultivation, those
which when cultivated yield the least return, in proportion
to the labor required for their culture, will always regulate
the price of agricultural produce; and all other lands will
pay a rent simply equivalent to the excess of their produce
over this minimum. Whatever unguarded expressions may
have been occasionally used in describing the law of rent,
these two propositions are all that was ever intended by it.
If, indeed, Mr. Carey could show that the return to labor
from the land, agricultural skill and science being supposed
the same, is not a diminishing return, he would overthrow a
principle much more fundamental than any law of rent.
But in this he has wholly failed.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Another objection taken against the law of diminishing
returns, and so against the law of rent, is that the potential increase
of food, e.g., of a grain of wheat, is far greater than
that of man.</span><SPAN id="noteref_183" name="noteref_183" href="#note_183"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">183</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
No one disputes the fact that one grain of wheat
can reproduce itself more times than man, and that too in a
geometric increase; but not without land. A grain of wheat
needs land in which it can multiply itself, and this necessary
element of its increase is limited; and it is the very thing
which limits the multiplication of the grains of wheat. On
the same piece of land, one can not get more than what comes
from one act of reproduction in the grain. If one grain produces
100 of its kind, doubling the capital will not repeatedly
cause a geometric increase in the ratio of reproduction of each
grain on this same land, so that one grain, by one process, produces
of its kind 200, 400, 800, or 1,600, because you can not
multiply the land in any such ratio as would accompany this
potential reduplication of the grain. This objection would not
seem worth answering, were it not that it furnishes some difficulty
to really honest inquirers.
</span>
<p>
Others, again, allege as an objection against Ricardo, that
if all land were of equal fertility it might still yield a rent.
But Ricardo says precisely the same. It is also distinctly a
portion of Ricardo's doctrine that, even apart from differences
of situation, the land of a country supposed to be of
uniform fertility would, all of it, on a certain supposition,
pay rent, namely, if the demand of the community required
that it should all be cultivated, and cultivated beyond the
point at which a further application of capital begins to be
attended with a smaller proportional return.</p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
This is simply the question, before discussed, whether, if
only one class of land were cultivated, some agricultural capital
would pay rent or not. It all depends on the fact whether
population—and so the demand for food—has increased to the
point where it calls out a recognition of the diminishing productiveness
of the soil. In that case different capitals would
be invested, so that there would be different returns to the
same amount of capital; and the prior or more advantageous
investments of capital on the land would yield more than the
ordinary rate of profit, which could be claimed as rent.
</span></p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
A. L. Perry</span><SPAN id="noteref_184" name="noteref_184" href="#note_184"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">184</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> admits the law of diminishing returns, but
holds that, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">as land is capital, and as every form of capital
may be loaned or rented, and thus become fruitful in the hands
of another, the rent of land does not differ essentially in its
nature from the rent of buildings in cities, or from the interest
of money.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Henry George admits Ricardo's law of rent to its
full extent, but very curiously says: </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Irrespective of the increase
of population, the effect of improvements in methods of
production and exchange is to increase rent.... The effect of
labor-saving improvements will be to increase the production
of wealth. Now, for the production of wealth, two things are
required, labor and land. Therefore, the effect of labor-saving
improvements will be to </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">extend the demand for land</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%">, and,
wherever the limit of the quality of land in use is reached, to
bring into cultivation lands of less natural productiveness, or
to extend cultivation on the same lands to a point of lower
natural productiveness. And thus, while the primary effect of
labor-saving improvements is to increase the power of labor,
the secondary effect is to extend cultivation, and, where this
lowers the margin of cultivation, to increase rent.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><SPAN id="noteref_185" name="noteref_185" href="#note_185"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">185</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> Francis
Bowen</span><SPAN id="noteref_186" name="noteref_186" href="#note_186"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">186</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> rejects Ricardo's law, and says, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Rent depends, not
on the increase, but on the distribution, of the population</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">—asserting
that the existence of large cities and towns determines
the amount of rent paid by neighboring land.</span><SPAN id="noteref_187" name="noteref_187" href="#note_187"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">187</span></span></SPAN></p>
<SPAN name="toc116" id="toc116"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 6. Rent does not enter into the Cost of Production of Agricultural Produce.</span></h3>
<p>
Rent does not really form any part of the expenses
of [agricultural] production, or of the advances of the capitalist.
The grounds on which this assertion was made are
now apparent. It is true that all tenant-farmers, and many
other classes of producers, pay rent. But we have now seen
that whoever cultivates land, paying a rent for it, gets in return
for his rent an instrument of superior power to other
instruments of the same kind for which no rent is paid. The
superiority of the instrument is in exact proportion to the
rent paid for it. If a few persons had steam-engines of superior
power to all others in existence, but limited by physical
laws to a number short of the demand, the rent which a
manufacturer would be willing to pay for one of these steam-engines
could not be looked upon as an addition to his outlay,
because by the use of it he would save in his other expenses
the equivalent of what it cost him: without it he could not
do the same quantity of work, unless at an additional expense
equal to the rent. The same thing is true of land.
The real expenses of production are those incurred on the
worst land, or by the capital employed in the least favorable
circumstances. This land or capital pays, as we have seen,
no rent, but the expenses to which it is subject cause all
other land or agricultural capital to be subjected to an equivalent
expense in the form of rent. Whoever does pay rent
gets back its full value in extra advantages, and the rent
which he pays does not place him in a worse position than,
but only in the same position as, his fellow-producer who pays
no rent, but whose instrument is one of inferior efficiency.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Soils are of every grade: some, which if cultivated, might
replace the capital, but give no profit; some give a slight
but not an ordinary profit; some, the ordinary profit. That
is, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">there is a point up to which it is profitable to cultivate,
and beyond which it is not profitable to cultivate. The price
of corn will not, for any long time, remain at a higher rate
than is sufficient to cover with ordinary profit the cost of that
portion of the general crop which is raised at greatest
expense.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><SPAN id="noteref_188" name="noteref_188" href="#note_188"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">188</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
For similar reasons the price will not remain at a
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
lower rate. If, then, the cost of production of grain is determined
by that land which replaces the capital, yields only the
ordinary profit, and pays no rent, rent forms no part of this
cost, since that land does not and can not pay any rent.
McLeod,</span><SPAN id="noteref_189" name="noteref_189" href="#note_189"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">189</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
however, says it is not the cost of production which
regulates the value of agricultural produce, but the value which
regulates the cost.
</span>
<!--book-->
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />