<SPAN name="toc117" id="toc117"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="pdf118" id="pdf118"></SPAN>
<h1><span>Book III. Exchange.</span></h1>
<SPAN name="toc119" id="toc119"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="pdf120" id="pdf120"></SPAN>
<h2><span>Chapter I. Of Value.</span></h2>
<SPAN name="toc121" id="toc121"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 1. Definitions of Value in Use, Exchange Value, and Price.</span></h3>
<p>
It is evident that, of the two great departments of
Political Economy, the production of wealth and its distribution,
the consideration of Value has to do with the latter
alone; and with that only so far as competition, and not
usage or custom, is the distributing agency.</p>
<p>
The use of a thing, in political economy, means its capacity
to satisfy a desire, or serve a purpose. Diamonds
have this capacity in a high degree, and, unless they had it,
would not bear any price. Value in use, or, as Mr. De Quincey
calls it, <span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-style: italic">teleologic</span></span> value, is the extreme limit of value in
exchange. The exchange value of a thing may fall short, to
any amount, of its value in use; but that it can ever exceed
the value in use implies a contradiction; it supposes that
persons will give, to possess a thing, more than the utmost
value which they themselves put upon it, as a means of gratifying
their inclinations.</p>
<p>
The word Value, when used without adjunct, always
means, in political economy, value in exchange.</p>
<p>
Exchange value requires to be distinguished from Price.
Writers have employed Price to express the value of a thing
in relation to money—the quantity of money for which it
will exchange. By the price of a thing, therefore, we shall
henceforth understand its value in money; by the value, or
exchange value of a thing, its general power of purchasing;
the command which its possession gives over purchasable
commodities in general. What is meant by command over
commodities in general? The same thing exchanges for a
greater quantity of some commodities, and for a very small
quantity of others. A coat may exchange for less bread this
year than last, if the harvest has been bad, but for more glass
or iron, if a tax has been taken off those commodities, or an
improvement made in their manufacture. Has the value of
the coat, under these circumstances, fallen or risen? It is
impossible to say: all that can be said is, that it has fallen in
relation to one thing, and risen in respect to another. Suppose,
for example, that an invention has been made in machinery,
by which broadcloth could be woven at half the
former cost. The effect of this would be to lower the value
of a coat, and, if lowered by this cause, it would be lowered
not in relation to bread only or to glass only, but to all purchasable
things, except such as happened to be affected at
the very time by a similar depressing cause. Those [changes]
which originate in the commodities with which we compare
it affect its value in relation to those commodities; but those
which originate in itself affect its value in relation to all
commodities.</p>
<p>
There is such a thing as a general rise of prices. All
commodities may rise in their money price. But there can
not be a general rise of values. It is a contradiction in
terms. A can only rise in value by exchanging for a greater
quantity of B and C; in which case these must exchange for
a smaller quantity of A. All things can not rise relatively
to one another. If one half of the commodities in the market
rise in exchange value, the very terms imply a fall of the
other half; and, reciprocally, the fall implies a rise. Things
which are exchanged for one another can no more all fall, or
all rise, than a dozen runners can each outrun all the rest, or
a hundred trees all overtop one another. A general rise or a
general fall of prices is merely tantamount to an alteration
in the value of money, and is a matter of complete indifference,
save in so far as it affects existing contracts for receiving
and paying fixed pecuniary amounts.</p>
<p>
Before commencing the inquiry into the laws of value
and price, I have one further observation to make. I must
give warning, once for all, that the cases I contemplate are
those in which values and prices are determined by competition
alone. In so far only as they are thus determined, can
they be reduced to any assignable law. The buyers must be
supposed as studious to buy cheap as the sellers to sell dear.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
The reader is advised to study the definitions of value given
by other writers. Cairnes</span><SPAN id="noteref_190" name="noteref_190" href="#note_190"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">190</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> defines value as </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the ratio in which
commodities in open market are exchanged against each other.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
F. A. Walker</span><SPAN id="noteref_191" name="noteref_191" href="#note_191"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">191</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> holds that </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">value is the power which an article
confers upon its possessor, irrespective of legal authority or
personal sentiments, of commanding, in exchange for itself,
the labor, or the products of the labor, of others.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Carey</span><SPAN id="noteref_192" name="noteref_192" href="#note_192"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">192</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
says, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Value is the measure of the resistance to be overcome
in obtaining those commodities or things required for our purposes—of
the power of nature over man.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Value is thus, with
him, the antithesis of wealth, which is (according to Carey) the
power of man over nature. In this school, value is the service
rendered by any one who supplies the article for the use
of another. This is also Bastiat's idea,</span><SPAN id="noteref_193" name="noteref_193" href="#note_193"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">193</span></span></SPAN> <span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span lang="fr" class="tei tei-foreign" xml:lang="fr"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">le rapport de deux
services échangés</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Following Bastiat, A. L.
Perry</span><SPAN id="noteref_194" name="noteref_194" href="#note_194"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">194</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> defines
value as </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">always and everywhere the relation of mutual purchase
established between two services by their exchange.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
Roscher</span><SPAN id="noteref_195" name="noteref_195" href="#note_195"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">195</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> explains exchange value as </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the quality which makes
them exchangeable against other goods.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> He also makes a
distinction between utility and value in use: </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Utility is a
quality of things themselves, in relation, it is true, to human
wants. Value in use is a quality imputed to them, the result
of man's thought, or his view of them. Thus, for instance, in
a beleaguered city, the stores of food do not increase in utility,
but their value in use does.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Levasseur</span><SPAN id="noteref_196" name="noteref_196" href="#note_196"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">196</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> regards value as </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the
relation resulting from exchange</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">—</span><span lang="fr" class="tei tei-foreign" xml:lang="fr"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">le
rapport resultant de l'échange</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">. Cherbuliez</span><SPAN id="noteref_197" name="noteref_197" href="#note_197"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">197</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> asserts that </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the
value of a product or
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
of a service can be expressed only as the products or services
which it obtains in exchange.... If I exchange the thing A
against B, A is the value of B, B is the value of A.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
Jevons</span><SPAN id="noteref_198" name="noteref_198" href="#note_198"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">198</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
defines value as </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">proportion in exchange.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span>
<SPAN name="toc122" id="toc122"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 2. Conditions of Value: Utility, Difficulty of Attainment, and Transferableness.</span></h3>
<p>
That a thing may have any value in exchange, two
conditions are necessary. 1. It must be of some use; that is
(as already explained), it must conduce to some purpose, satisfy
some desire. No one will pay a price, or part with anything
which serves some of his purposes, to obtain a thing
which serves none of them. 2. But, secondly, the thing
must not only have some utility, there must also be some
difficulty in its attainment.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
The question is one as to the conditions essential to the existence
of any value. Very justly Cairnes</span><SPAN id="noteref_199" name="noteref_199" href="#note_199"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">199</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> adds also a third
condition, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the possibility of transferring the possession of the
articles which are the subject of the exchange.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> For instance,
a cargo of wheat at the bottom of the sea has value in use and
difficulty of attainment, but it is not transferable. Jevons (following
J. B. Say) maintains that </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">value depends entirely on
utility.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> If utility means the power to satisfy a desire, things
which merely have utility and no difficulty of attainment could
have no exchange value.</span><SPAN id="noteref_200" name="noteref_200" href="#note_200"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">200</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> F. A. Walker</span><SPAN id="noteref_201" name="noteref_201" href="#note_201"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">201</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> believes that </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">value
depends wholly on the relation between demand and supply.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
Carey</span><SPAN id="noteref_202" name="noteref_202" href="#note_202"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">202</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> holds that value depends merely on the cost of reproduction
of the given article. Roscher</span><SPAN id="noteref_203" name="noteref_203" href="#note_203"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">203</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> finds that exchange value
is </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">based on a combination of value in use with cost value.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
Cherbuliez</span><SPAN id="noteref_204" name="noteref_204" href="#note_204"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">204</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
calls the conditions of value two, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the ability to
give satisfaction, and inability of attainment without effort.
The first element is subjective; it is determined wholly by the
needs or desires of the parties to the exchange. The second is
objective; it depends upon material considerations, which are
the conditions of the existence of the thing, and upon which the
needs of the persons exchanging have no influence whatever.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
It is, as usual, one of Cherbuliez's clear expositions. A. L.
Perry</span><SPAN id="noteref_205" name="noteref_205" href="#note_205"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">205</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
states that, </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">while value always takes its rise in the
</span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">desires</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> of men, it is never realized except through the
</span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">efforts</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> of men, and through these efforts as mutually exchanged.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span>
<p>
The difficulty of attainment which determines value is
not always the same kind of difficulty: (1.) It sometimes
consists in an absolute limitation of the supply. There are
things of which it is physically impossible to increase the
quantity beyond certain narrow limits. Such are those wines
which can be grown only in peculiar circumstances of soil, climate,
and exposure. Such also are ancient sculptures; pictures
by the old masters; rare books or coins, or other articles of
antiquarian curiosity. Among such may also be reckoned
houses and building-ground, in a town of definite extent.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
De Quincey</span><SPAN id="noteref_206" name="noteref_206" href="#note_206"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">206</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">
has presented some ingenious diagrams to
represent the operations of the two constituents of value in
each of the three following cases: U represents the
power of the article to satisfy some desire, and D
difficulty of attainment. In the first case, exchange
value is not hindered by D from going up to any
height, and so it rises and falls entirely according
to the force of U. D being practically infinite,
the horizontal line, exchange value, is not kept
down by D, but it rises just as far as U, the desires
of purchasers, may carry it.
</span>
<p></p>
<ANTIMG src="images/value-1.png" width-obs="220" height-obs="386" alt="Illustration: Vertical line D, paralleled by shorter vertical line U, D and U connected at top of U by horizontal line." />
<p>
(2.) But there is another category (embracing the majority
of all things that are bought and sold), in which the obstacle
to attainment consists only in the labor and expense
requisite to produce the commodity. Without a certain
labor and expense it can not be had; but, when any one is
willing to incur these, there needs be no limit to the multiplication
of the product. If there were laborers enough and
machinery enough, cottons, woolens, or linens might be produced
by thousands of yards for every single yard now manufactured.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
In case (2) the horizontal line, representing
exchange value, follows the force of D entirely.
The utility of the article is very great, but the
value is only limited by the difficulty of obtaining
it. So far as U is concerned, exchange
value can go up a great distance, but will go no
higher than the point where the article can be
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
obtained. The dotted lines underneath the horizontal line indicate
that the exchange value of articles in this class tend to
fall in value.
</span>
<p></p>
<ANTIMG src="images/value-2.png" width-obs="266" height-obs="361" alt="Illustration: Parallel vertical lines U and D, U being longer, joined by several horizontal lines of Exchange Value." />
<p>
(3.) There is a third case, intermediate between the two
preceding, and rather more complex, which I shall at present
merely indicate, but the importance of which in political
economy is extremely great. There are commodities which
can be multiplied to an indefinite extent by labor and expenditure,
but not by a fixed amount of labor and expenditure.
Only a limited quantity can be produced at a given
cost; if more is wanted, it must be produced at a greater
cost. To this class, as has been often repeated, agricultural
produce belongs, and generally all the rude produce of the
earth; and this peculiarity is a source of very important consequences;
one of which is the necessity of a limit to population;
and another, the payment of rent.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
In case (3) articles like agricultural produce have a very
great power to satisfy desires, and if scarce would
have a high value. So far as U is concerned, here
also, as in case (2), exchange value might mount
upward to almost any height, but it can go no
higher than D permits. In commodities of this
class, affected by the law of diminishing returns,
the tendency is for D to increase, and so for exchange
value to rise, as indicated by the dotted lines
above that of the exchange value.
</span>
<p></p>
<ANTIMG src="images/value-3.png" width-obs="221" height-obs="365" alt="Illustration: Same as before." />
<SPAN name="toc123" id="toc123"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="Book_III_Chapter_I_Section_3" id="Book_III_Chapter_I_Section_3" class="tei tei-anchor"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 3. Commodities limited in Quantity by the law of Demand and Supply: General working of this Law.</span></h3>
<p>
These being the three classes, in one or other of
which all things that are bought and sold must take their
place, we shall consider them in their order. And first, of
things absolutely limited in quantity, such as ancient sculptures
or pictures.</p>
<p>
Of such things it is commonly said that their value depends
on their scarcity; others say that the value depends
on the demand and supply. But this statement requires
much explanation. The supply of a commodity is an intelligible
expression: it means the quantity offered for sale;
the quantity that is to be had, at a given time and place, by
those who wish to purchase it. But what is meant by the
demand? Not the mere desire for the commodity. A beggar
may desire a diamond; but his desire, however great,
will have no influence on the price. Writers have therefore
given a more limited sense to demand, and have defined
it, the wish to possess, combined with the power of
purchasing.<SPAN id="noteref_207" name="noteref_207" href="#note_207"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">207</span></span></SPAN>
To distinguish demand in this technical sense from
the demand which is synonymous with desire, they call the
former <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">effectual</span></em> demand.</p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
General supply consists in the commodities offered in exchange
for other commodities; general demand likewise, if no
money exists, consists in the commodities offered as purchasing
power in exchange for other commodities. That is, one can
not increase the demand for certain things without increasing
the supply of some articles which will be received in exchange
for the desired commodities. Demand is based upon the production
of articles having exchange value, in its economic
sense; and the measure of this demand is necessarily the quantity
of commodities offered in exchange for the desired goods.
General demand and supply are thus reciprocal to each other.
But as soon as money, or general purchasing power, is introduced,
Mr. Cairnes</span><SPAN id="noteref_208" name="noteref_208" href="#note_208"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">208</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> defines </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">demand as the desire for commodities
or services, seeking its end by an offer of general purchasing
power; and supply, as the desire for general purchasing
power, seeking its end by an offer of specific commodities or
services.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> But many persons find a difficulty because they
insist upon separating the idea of supply from that of demand,
owing to the fact that producers seem to be a distinct class in
the community, different from consumers. That they are in
reality the same persons can be easily explained by the following
statement: </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">A certain number of people, A, B, C, D, E,
F, etc., are engaged in industrial occupations—A produces for
B, C, D, E, F; B for A, C, D, E, F; C for A, B, D, E, F, and
so on. In each case the producer and the consumers are distinct,
and hence, by a very natural fallacy, it is concluded that
the whole body of consumers is distinct from the whole body of
producers, whereas they consist of precisely the same persons.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span></p>
<p class="tei tei-p" style="margin-bottom: 0.90em"><span style="font-size: 90%">
But in regard to demand and supply of particular commodities
(not general demand and supply), the increase of the demand
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
is not necessarily followed by an increased supply, or
</span><span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">vice versa</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">. Out of the total production (which constitutes
general demand) a varying amount, sometimes more, sometimes
less, may be directed by the desires of men to the purchase of
some given thing. This should be borne in mind, in connection
with the future discussion of over-production. The identity
of general demand with general supply shows there can be
no general over-production: but so long as there exists the possibility
that the demand for a particular commodity may diminish
without a corresponding effect being thereby produced on
the supply of that commodity, by a necessary connection, we
see that there may be over-production of particular commodities;
that is, a production in excess of the demand.
</span></p>
<p>
The proper mathematical analogy [between demand and
supply] is that of an <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">equation</span></em>. If unequal at any moment,
competition equalizes them, and the manner in which this is
done is by an adjustment of the value. If the demand increases,
the value rises; if the demand diminishes, the value
falls; again, if the supply falls off, the value rises; and falls,
if the supply is increased. The rise or the fall continues
until the demand and supply are again equal to one another:
and the value which a commodity will bring in any market
is no other than the value which, in that market, gives a
demand just sufficient to carry off the existing or expected
supply.</p>
<p>
Mr. Cairnes<SPAN id="noteref_209" name="noteref_209" href="#note_209"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">209</span></span></SPAN> finally defined market value as the price
<span class="tei tei-q">“which is sufficient, and no more than sufficient, to carry the
existing supply over, with such a surplus as circumstances
may render advisable, to meet the new supplies forthcoming,”</span>
which is nothing more than a paraphrase of the words <span class="tei tei-q">“existing
or expected supply”</span> just used by Mr. Mill. It seems
unnecessary, therefore, that Mr. Cairnes should have added:
<span class="tei tei-q">“According to Mr. Mill, the <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">actual market price</span></em> is the price
which equalizes supply and demand in a given market; as I
view the case, the <span class="tei tei-q">‘proper market price’</span> is the price which
equalizes supply and demand, <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">not</span></em> as existing in the particular
market, but in the larger sense which I have assigned to the
terms. To this price the <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">actual market price</span></em> will, according
to my view, approximate, in proportion to the intelligence and
knowledge of the dealers.”</span></p>
<p>
Adam Smith, who introduced the expression <span class="tei tei-q">“effectual
demand,”</span> employed it to denote the demand of those who
are willing and able to give for the commodity what he calls
its natural price—that is, the price which will enable it to be
permanently produced and brought to market.<SPAN id="noteref_210" name="noteref_210" href="#note_210"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">210</span></span></SPAN></p>
<p>
This, then, is the Law of Value, with respect to all commodities
not susceptible of being multiplied at pleasure.</p>
<SPAN name="toc124" id="toc124"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 4. Miscellaneous Cases falling under this Law.</span></h3>
<p>
There are but few commodities which are naturally
and necessarily limited in supply. But any commodity
whatever may be artificially so. The monopolist can fix the
value as high as he pleases, short of what the consumer either
could not or would not pay; but he can only do so by limiting
the supply. Monopoly value, therefore, does not depend
on any peculiar principle, but is a mere variety of the ordinary
case of demand and supply.</p>
<p>
Again, though there are few commodities which are at
all times and forever unsusceptible of increase of supply,
any commodity whatever may be temporarily so; and with
some commodities this is habitually the case. Agricultural
produce, for example, can not be increased in quantity before
the next harvest; the quantity of corn already existing in
the world is all that can be had for sometimes a year to
come. During that interval, corn is practically assimilated
to things of which the quantity can not be increased. In the
case of most commodities, it requires a certain time to increase
their quantity; and if the demand increases, then,
until a corresponding supply can be brought forward, that
is, until the supply can accommodate itself to the demand,
the value will so rise as to accommodate the demand to the
supply.</p>
<p>
There is another case the exact converse of this. There
are some articles of which the supply may be indefinitely
increased, but can not be rapidly diminished. There are
things so durable that the quantity in existence is at all times
very great in comparison with the annual produce. Gold
and the more durable metals are things of this sort, and
also houses. The supply of such things might be at once
diminished by destroying them; but to do this could only
be the interest of the possessor if he had a monopoly of the
article, and could repay himself for the destruction of a part
by the increased value of the remainder. The value, therefore,
of such things may continue for a long time so low,
either from excess of supply or falling off in the demand, as
to put a complete stop to further production; the diminution
of supply by wearing out being so slow a process that a
long time is requisite, even under a total suspension of production,
to restore the original value. During that interval
the value will be regulated solely by supply and demand,
and will rise very gradually as the existing stock wears out,
until there is again a remunerating value, and production
resumes its course.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
The total value of gold and silver in the world is variously
estimated at from $10,000,000,000 to $14,000,000,000; while
the annual production of both gold and silver in the world
during 1882</span><SPAN id="noteref_211" name="noteref_211" href="#note_211"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">211</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> was only $212,000,000. The loss of gold by
abrasion is about 1/1000 annually, and of silver about 1/700, but
much depends on the size of the coin. A change in the annual
production of the precious metals can have a perceptible effect
on their value only after such a time as will permit the change
to affect the existing quantity in a way somewhat comparable
with its previous amount. The quantity, however, of wheat
produced is nearly all consumed between harvests; and the
annual supply bears a very large ratio to the existing quantity.
Consequently the price of wheat will be very seriously affected
by the quantity coming from the annual product.
</span>
<p>
Finally, there are commodities of which, though capable
of being increased or diminished to a great and even an unlimited
extent, the value never depends upon anything but
demand and supply. This is the case, in particular, with the
commodity Labor, of the value of which we have treated
copiously in the preceding book; and there are many cases
besides in which we shall find it necessary to call in this
principle to solve difficult questions of exchange value. This
will be particularly exemplified when we treat of International
Values; that is, of the terms of interchange between
things produced in different countries, or, to speak more generally,
in distant places.</p>
<SPAN name="toc125" id="toc125"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 5. Commodities which are Susceptible of Indefinite Multiplication without Increase of Cost. Law of their Value Cost of Production.</span></h3>
<p>
When the production of a commodity is the effect of
labor and expenditure, whether the commodity is susceptible
of unlimited multiplication or not, there is a minimum value
which is the essential condition of its being permanently
produced. The value at any particular time is the result of
supply and demand, and is always that which is necessary
to create a market for the existing supply. But unless that
value is sufficient to repay the Cost of Production, and to
afford, besides, the ordinary expectation of profit, the commodity
will not continue to be produced. Capitalists will
not go on permanently producing at a loss. When such
profit is evidently not to be had, if people do not actually
withdraw their capital, they at least abstain from replacing
it when consumed. The cost of production, together with
the ordinary profit, may, therefore, be called the <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">necessary</span></em>
price or value of all things made by labor and capital. Nobody
willingly produces in the prospect of loss.</p>
<p>
When a commodity is not only made by labor and capital,
but can be made by them in indefinite quantity, this
Necessary Value, the minimum with which the producers
will be content, is also, if competition is free and active, the
maximum which they can expect. If the value of a commodity
is such that it repays the cost of production not only
with the customary but with a higher rate of profit, capital
rushes to share in this extra gain, and, by increasing the supply
of the article, reduces its value. This is not a mere supposition
or surmise, but a fact familiar to those conversant
with commercial operations. Whenever a new line of business
presents itself, offering a hope of unusual profits, and
whenever any established trade or manufacture is believed
to be yielding a greater profit than customary, there is sure
to be in a short time so large a production or importation of
the commodity as not only destroys the extra profit, but
generally goes beyond the mark, and sinks the value as much
too low as it had before been raised too high, until the over-supply
is corrected by a total or partial suspension of further
production. As already intimated,<SPAN id="noteref_212" name="noteref_212" href="#note_212"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">212</span></span></SPAN> these variations in the
quantity produced do not presuppose or require that any
person should change his employment. Those whose business
is thriving, increase their produce by availing themselves
more largely of their credit, while those who are not
making the ordinary profit, restrict their operations, and (in
manufacturing phrase) work short time. In this mode is
surely and speedily effected the equalization, not of profits,
perhaps, but of the expectations of profit, in different occupations.</p>
<p>
As a general rule, then, things tend to exchange for one
another at such values as will enable each producer to be
repaid the cost of production with the ordinary profit; in
other words, such as will give to all producers the same rate
of profit on their outlay. But in order that the profit may
be equal where the outlay, that is, the cost of production,
is equal, things must on the average exchange for one another
in the ratio of their cost of production; things of
which the cost of production is the same, must be of the
same value.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Mr. Mill has here used cost of production almost exactly
in the sense of cost of labor, and as excluding profit (while in
the next chapter he includes some part of profit in the analysis).
It will be well, for the sake of definiteness, to collect the
phrases above in which he describes cost of production: </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">Unless
that value is sufficient to repay the cost of production, and
to afford, </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">besides</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%">, the ordinary expectation of profit, the commodity
will not continue to be produced</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">; </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the cost of production,
</span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">together with</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> the ordinary profit, may therefore be
called the </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">necessary</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> price, or value</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">; </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">it repays the cost of
production, not only </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">with</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> the customary, but </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">with</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> a higher
rate of profit</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">; </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the cost of production with the ordinary
profit—in other words, such as will give to all producers the
same rate of profit on their outlay</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">; </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">that the profit may be
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
equal where </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">the outlay, that is, the cost of production</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%">, is equal.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">
This is a view which distinctly uses cost of production in the
sense of the outlay to the capitalist, or cost of labor. In no
other way can profit vary with </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">cost of production</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> than in the
sense that it is what a given article </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">costs to the capitalist</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%">;
but that is Mr. Mill's definition of cost of labor (p. </span><SPAN href="#Pg227" class="tei tei-ref"><span style="font-size: 90%">227</span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%">).
It is, however, very puzzling when in the next section he speaks of
</span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">the natural value, that is, the cost of production.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> Above,
value included cost of production and profit also. Having
thus pointed out what is Mr. Mill's conception of cost of production,
it will remain for us in the next chapter to consider
whether any other view of it is more satisfactory.
</span>
<p>
Adam Smith and Ricardo have called that value of a
thing which is proportional to its cost of production, its
Natural Value (or its Natural Price). They meant by this,
the point about which the value oscillates, and to which it
always tends to return; the center value, toward which, as
Adam Smith expresses it, the market value of a thing is
constantly gravitating; and any deviation from which is
but a temporary irregularity which, the moment it exists,
sets forces in motion tending to correct it. On an average
of years sufficient to enable the oscillations on one side of
the central line to be compensated by those on the other,
the market value agrees with the natural value; but it very
seldom coincides exactly with it at any particular time. The
sea everywhere tends to a level, but it never is at an exact
level; its surface is always ruffled by waves, and often agitated
by storms. It is enough that no point, at least in the
open sea, is permanently higher than another. Each place
is alternately elevated and depressed; but the ocean preserves
its level.</p>
<SPAN name="toc126" id="toc126"></SPAN>
<h3><span>§ 6. The Value of these Commodities confirm, in the long run, to their Cost of Production through the operation of Demand and Supply.</span></h3>
<p>
The latent influence by which the values of things
are made to conform in the long run to the cost of production
is the variation that would otherwise take place in the
supply of the commodity. The supply would be increased
if the thing continued to sell above the ratio of its cost of production,
and would be diminished if it fell below that ratio.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
If one dollar covers the expense of making one spade, then
when a spade, by virtue of a sudden demand, rises in value to one
</span><span style="font-size: 90%">
dollar and ten cents, the manufacturers get an extra profit of
ten cents. This could not long remain so, because other capital
would enter this industry, and so increase the supply that
one spade would sell for only one dollar; then all would receive
the average profit. If, owing to a cessation of demand for
spades, the price fell to ninety cents, then the manufacturers
would lose ten cents on each one made and sold. Thereupon
they would cease to do a losing business, capital would be
withdrawn, and spades would not be made until the supply was
suited to the necessary expense of making them (one dollar).
In this way, whenever there is a departure of the value from
the normal cost, there is set in motion </span><span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">ipso facto</span></span><span style="font-size: 90%"> a series of
forces which automatically restores the value to that cost. So
here again we see the nature of an economic law: the value
may not often correspond exactly with cost of production, but
there is a </span><em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-size: 90%; font-style: italic">tendency</span></em><span style="font-size: 90%"> in all values to conform to that cost, and
this tendency they irresistibly obey. A body possessing weight
does not move downward under all circumstances (stones may
be thrown upward), but the law of gravitation holds true, nevertheless.
</span>
<p>
There is no need that there should be any actual alteration
of supply; and when there is, the alteration, if permanent,
is not the cause but the consequence of the alteration
in value. If, indeed, the supply <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">could</span></em> not be increased, no
diminution in the cost of production would lower the value;
but there is by no means any necessity that it <em class="tei tei-emph"><span style="font-style: italic">should</span></em>. The
mere possibility often suffices; the dealers are aware of what
would happen, and their mutual competition makes them
anticipate the result by lowering the price.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Before the electric light was yet known as a feasible means
of lighting (in 1878), the mere rumor of Edison's invention,
before it was made public, and long before it became practicable,
caused a serious fall in the price of gas stocks.
</span>
<p>
It is, therefore, strictly correct to say that the value of
things which can be increased in quantity at pleasure does
not depend (except accidentally, and during the time necessary
for production to adjust itself) upon demand and supply;
on the contrary, demand and supply depend upon it.
There is a demand for a certain quantity of the commodity
at its natural or cost value, and to that the supply in the
long run endeavors to conform.</p>
<span style="font-size: 90%">
Mr. Cairnes</span><SPAN id="noteref_213" name="noteref_213" href="#note_213"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">213</span></span></SPAN><span style="font-size: 90%"> fitly says: </span><span class="tei tei-q"><span style="font-size: 90%">“</span><span style="font-size: 90%">The supply of a commodity always
tends to adapt itself to the demand at the normal price.
I may here say briefly that by the normal price of a commodity
I mean that price which suffices, and no more than suffices,
to yield to the producers what is considered to be the
average and usual remuneration on such sacrifices as they
undergo.</span><span style="font-size: 90%">”</span></span>
<p>
When at any time it fails of so conforming, it is either
from miscalculation, or from a change in some of the elements
of the problem; either in the natural value, that is,
in the cost of production, or in the demand, from an alteration
in public taste, or in the number or wealth of the consumers.
If a value different from the natural value be necessary
to make the demand equal to the supply, the market
value will deviate from the natural value; but only for a
time, for the permanent tendency of supply is to conform
itself to the demand which is found by experience to exist
for the commodity when selling at its natural value. If the
supply is either more or less than this, it is so accidentally,
and affords either more or less than the ordinary rate of
profit, which, under free and active competition, can not
long continue to be the case.</p>
<p>
To recapitulate: demand and supply govern the value
of all things which can not be indefinitely increased; except
that even for them, when produced by industry, there is a
minimum value, determined by the cost of production. But
in all things which admit of indefinite multiplication, demand
and supply only determine the perturbations of value
during a period which can not exceed the length of time
necessary for altering the supply. While thus ruling the
oscillations of value, they themselves obey a superior force,
which makes value gravitate toward Cost of Production, and
which would settle it and keep it there, if fresh disturbing
influences were not continually arising to make it again deviate.</p>
<hr class="page" />
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />