<p>As seen from the economic point of view, leisure, considered as an
employment, is closely allied in kind with the life of exploit; and the
achievements which characterise a life of leisure, and which remain as its
decorous criteria, have much in common with the trophies of exploit. But
leisure in the narrower sense, as distinct from exploit and from any
ostensibly productive employment of effort on objects which are of no
intrinsic use, does not commonly leave a material product. The criteria of
a past performance of leisure therefore commonly take the form of
"immaterial" goods. Such immaterial evidences of past leisure are
quasi-scholarly or quasi-artistic accomplishments and a knowledge of
processes and incidents which do not conduce directly to the furtherance
of human life. So, for instance, in our time there is the knowledge of the
dead languages and the occult sciences; of correct spelling; of syntax and
prosody; of the various forms of domestic music and other household art;
of the latest properties of dress, furniture, and equipage; of games,
sports, and fancy-bred animals, such as dogs and race-horses. In all these
branches of knowledge the initial motive from which their acquisition
proceeded at the outset, and through which they first came into vogue, may
have been something quite different from the wish to show that one's time
had not been spent in industrial employment; but unless these
accomplishments had approved themselves as serviceable evidence of an
unproductive expenditure of time, they would not have survived and held
their place as conventional accomplishments of the leisure class.</p>
<p>These accomplishments may, in some sense, be classed as branches of
learning. Beside and beyond these there is a further range of social facts
which shade off from the region of learning into that of physical habit
and dexterity. Such are what is known as manners and breeding, polite
usage, decorum, and formal and ceremonial observances generally. This
class of facts are even more immediately and obtrusively presented to the
observation, and they therefore more widely and more imperatively insisted
on as required evidences of a reputable degree of leisure. It is worth
while to remark that all that class of ceremonial observances which are
classed under the general head of manners hold a more important place in
the esteem of men during the stage of culture at which conspicuous leisure
has the greatest vogue as a mark of reputability, than at later stages of
the cultural development. The barbarian of the quasi-peaceable stage of
industry is notoriously a more high-bred gentleman, in all that concerns
decorum, than any but the very exquisite among the men of a later age.
Indeed, it is well known, or at least it is currently believed, that
manners have progressively deteriorated as society has receded from the
patriarchal stage. Many a gentleman of the old school has been provoked to
remark regretfully upon the under-bred manners and bearing of even the
better classes in the modern industrial communities; and the decay of the
ceremonial code—or as it is otherwise called, the vulgarisation of
life—among the industrial classes proper has become one of the chief
enormities of latter-day civilisation in the eyes of all persons of
delicate sensibilities. The decay which the code has suffered at the hands
of a busy people testifies—all depreciation apart—to the fact
that decorum is a product and an exponent of leisure class life and
thrives in full measure only under a regime of status.</p>
<p>The origin, or better the derivation, of manners is no doubt, to be sought
elsewhere than in a conscious effort on the part of the well-mannered to
show that much time has been spent in acquiring them. The proximate end of
innovation and elaboration has been the higher effectiveness of the new
departure in point of beauty or of expressiveness. In great part the
ceremonial code of decorous usages owes its beginning and its growth to
the desire to conciliate or to show good-will, as anthropologists and
sociologists are in the habit of assuming, and this initial motive is
rarely if ever absent from the conduct of well-mannered persons at any
stage of the later development. Manners, we are told, are in part an
elaboration of gesture, and in part they are symbolical and
conventionalised survivals representing former acts of dominance or of
personal service or of personal contact. In large part they are an
expression of the relation of status,—a symbolic pantomime of
mastery on the one hand and of subservience on the other. Wherever at the
present time the predatory habit of mind, and the consequent attitude of
mastery and of subservience, gives its character to the accredited scheme
of life, there the importance of all punctilios of conduct is extreme, and
the assiduity with which the ceremonial observance of rank and titles is
attended to approaches closely to the ideal set by the barbarian of the
quasi-peaceable nomadic culture. Some of the Continental countries afford
good illustrations of this spiritual survival. In these communities the
archaic ideal is similarly approached as regards the esteem accorded to
manners as a fact of intrinsic worth.</p>
<p>Decorum set out with being symbol and pantomime and with having utility
only as an exponent of the facts and qualities symbolised; but it
presently suffered the transmutation which commonly passes over symbolical
facts in human intercourse. Manners presently came, in popular
apprehension, to be possessed of a substantial utility in themselves; they
acquired a sacramental character, in great measure independent of the
facts which they originally prefigured. Deviations from the code of
decorum have become intrinsically odious to all men, and good breeding is,
in everyday apprehension, not simply an adventitious mark of human
excellence, but an integral feature of the worthy human soul. There are
few things that so touch us with instinctive revulsion as a breach of
decorum; and so far have we progressed in the direction of imputing
intrinsic utility to the ceremonial observances of etiquette that few of
us, if any, can dissociate an offence against etiquette from a sense of
the substantial unworthiness of the offender. A breach of faith may be
condoned, but a breach of decorum can not. "Manners maketh man."</p>
<p>None the less, while manners have this intrinsic utility, in the
apprehension of the performer and the beholder alike, this sense of the
intrinsic rightness of decorum is only the proximate ground of the vogue
of manners and breeding. Their ulterior, economic ground is to be sought
in the honorific character of that leisure or non-productive employment of
time and effort without which good manners are not acquired. The knowledge
and habit of good form come only by long-continued use. Refined tastes,
manners, habits of life are a useful evidence of gentility, because good
breeding requires time, application and expense, and can therefore not be
compassed by those whose time and energy are taken up with work. A
knowledge of good form is prima facie evidence that that portion of the
well-bred person's life which is not spent under the observation of the
spectator has been worthily spent in acquiring accomplishments that are of
no lucrative effect. In the last analysis the value of manners lies in the
fact that they are the voucher of a life of leisure. Therefore,
conversely, since leisure is the conventional means of pecuniary repute,
the acquisition of some proficiency in decorum is incumbent on all who
aspire to a modicum of pecuniary decency.</p>
<p>So much of the honourable life of leisure as is not spent in the sight of
spectators can serve the purposes of reputability only in so far as it
leaves a tangible, visible result that can be put in evidence and can be
measured and compared with products of the same class exhibited by
competing aspirants for repute. Some such effect, in the way of leisurely
manners and carriage, etc., follows from simple persistent abstention from
work, even where the subject does not take thought of the matter and
studiously acquire an air of leisurely opulence and mastery. Especially
does it seem to be true that a life of leisure in this way persisted in
through several generations will leave a persistent, ascertainable effect
in the conformation of the person, and still more in his habitual bearing
and demeanour. But all the suggestions of a cumulative life of leisure,
and all the proficiency in decorum that comes by the way of passive
habituation, may be further improved upon by taking thought and
assiduously acquiring the marks of honourable leisure, and then carrying
the exhibition of these adventitious marks of exemption from employment
out in a strenuous and systematic discipline. Plainly, this is a point at
which a diligent application of effort and expenditure may materially
further the attainment of a decent proficiency in the leisure-class
properties. Conversely, the greater the degree of proficiency and the more
patent the evidence of a high degree of habituation to observances which
serve no lucrative or other directly useful purpose, the greater the
consumption of time and substance impliedly involved in their acquisition,
and the greater the resultant good repute. Hence under the competitive
struggle for proficiency in good manners, it comes about that much pains
in taken with the cultivation of habits of decorum; and hence the details
of decorum develop into a comprehensive discipline, conformity to which is
required of all who would be held blameless in point of repute. And hence,
on the other hand, this conspicuous leisure of which decorum is a
ramification grows gradually into a laborious drill in deportment and an
education in taste and discrimination as to what articles of consumption
are decorous and what are the decorous methods of consuming them.</p>
<p>In this connection it is worthy of notice that the possibility of
producing pathological and other idiosyncrasies of person and manner by
shrewd mimicry and a systematic drill have been turned to account in the
deliberate production of a cultured class—often with a very happy
effect. In this way, by the process vulgarly known as snobbery, a
syncopated evolution of gentle birth and breeding is achieved in the case
of a goodly number of families and lines of descent. This syncopated
gentle birth gives results which, in point of serviceability as a
leisure-class factor in the population, are in no wise substantially
inferior to others who may have had a longer but less arduous training in
the pecuniary properties.</p>
<p>There are, moreover, measureable degrees of conformity to the latest
accredited code of the punctilios as regards decorous means and methods of
consumption. Differences between one person and another in the degree of
conformity to the ideal in these respects can be compared, and persons may
be graded and scheduled with some accuracy and effect according to a
progressive scale of manners and breeding. The award of reputability in
this regard is commonly made in good faith, on the ground of conformity to
accepted canons of taste in the matters concerned, and without conscious
regard to the pecuniary standing or the degree of leisure practised by any
given candidate for reputability; but the canons of taste according to
which the award is made are constantly under the surveillance of the law
of conspicuous leisure, and are indeed constantly undergoing change and
revision to bring them into closer conformity with its requirements. So
that while the proximate ground of discrimination may be of another kind,
still the pervading principle and abiding test of good breeding is the
requirement of a substantial and patent waste of time. There may be some
considerable range of variation in detail within the scope of this
principle, but they are variations of form and expression, not of
substance.</p>
<p>Much of the courtesy of everyday intercourse is of course a direct
expression of consideration and kindly good-will, and this element of
conduct has for the most part no need of being traced back to any
underlying ground of reputability to explain either its presence or the
approval with which it is regarded; but the same is not true of the code
of properties. These latter are expressions of status. It is of course
sufficiently plain, to any one who cares to see, that our bearing towards
menials and other pecuniary dependent inferiors is the bearing of the
superior member in a relation of status, though its manifestation is often
greatly modified and softened from the original expression of crude
dominance. Similarly, our bearing towards superiors, and in great measure
towards equals, expresses a more or less conventionalised attitude of
subservience. Witness the masterful presence of the high-minded gentleman
or lady, which testifies to so much of dominance and independence of
economic circumstances, and which at the same time appeals with such
convincing force to our sense of what is right and gracious. It is among
this highest leisure class, who have no superiors and few peers, that
decorum finds its fullest and maturest expression; and it is this highest
class also that gives decorum that definite formulation which serves as a
canon of conduct for the classes beneath. And there also the code is most
obviously a code of status and shows most plainly its incompatibility with
all vulgarly productive work. A divine assurance and an imperious
complaisance, as of one habituated to require subservience and to take no
thought for the morrow, is the birthright and the criterion of the
gentleman at his best; and it is in popular apprehension even more than
that, for this demeanour is accepted as an intrinsic attribute of superior
worth, before which the base-born commoner delights to stoop and yield.</p>
<p>As has been indicated in an earlier chapter, there is reason to believe
that the institution of ownership has begun with the ownership of persons,
primarily women. The incentives to acquiring such property have apparently
been: (1) a propensity for dominance and coercion; (2) the utility of
these persons as evidence of the prowess of the owner; (3) the utility of
their services.</p>
<p>Personal service holds a peculiar place in the economic development.
During the stage of quasi-peaceable industry, and especially during the
earlier development of industry within the limits of this general stage,
the utility of their services seems commonly to be the dominant motive to
the acquisition of property in persons. Servants are valued for their
services. But the dominance of this motive is not due to a decline in the
absolute importance of the other two utilities possessed by servants. It
is rather that the altered circumstance of life accentuate the utility of
servants for this last-named purpose. Women and other slaves are highly
valued, both as an evidence of wealth and as a means of accumulating
wealth. Together with cattle, if the tribe is a pastoral one, they are the
usual form of investment for a profit. To such an extent may female
slavery give its character to the economic life under the quasi-peaceable
culture that the women even comes to serve as a unit of value among
peoples occupying this cultural stage—as for instance in Homeric
times. Where this is the case there need be little question but that the
basis of the industrial system is chattel slavery and that the women are
commonly slaves. The great, pervading human relation in such a system is
that of master and servant. The accepted evidence of wealth is the
possession of many women, and presently also of other slaves engaged in
attendance on their master's person and in producing goods for him.</p>
<p>A division of labour presently sets in, whereby personal service and
attendance on the master becomes the special office of a portion of the
servants, while those who are wholly employed in industrial occupations
proper are removed more and more from all immediate relation to the person
of their owner. At the same time those servants whose office is personal
service, including domestic duties, come gradually to be exempted from
productive industry carried on for gain.</p>
<p>This process of progressive exemption from the common run of industrial
employment will commonly begin with the exemption of the wife, or the
chief wife. After the community has advanced to settled habits of life,
wife-capture from hostile tribes becomes impracticable as a customary
source of supply. Where this cultural advance has been achieved, the chief
wife is ordinarily of gentle blood, and the fact of her being so will
hasten her exemption from vulgar employment. The manner in which the
concept of gentle blood originates, as well as the place which it occupies
in the development of marriage, cannot be discussed in this place. For the
purpose in hand it will be sufficient to say that gentle blood is blood
which has been ennobled by protracted contact with accumulated wealth or
unbroken prerogative. The women with these antecedents is preferred in
marriage, both for the sake of a resulting alliance with her powerful
relatives and because a superior worth is felt to inhere in blood which
has been associated with many goods and great power. She will still be her
husband's chattel, as she was her father's chattel before her purchase,
but she is at the same time of her father's gentle blood; and hence there
is a moral incongruity in her occupying herself with the debasing
employments of her fellow-servants. However completely she may be subject
to her master, and however inferior to the male members of the social
stratum in which her birth has placed her, the principle that gentility is
transmissible will act to place her above the common slave; and so soon as
this principle has acquired a prescriptive authority it will act to invest
her in some measure with that prerogative of leisure which is the chief
mark of gentility. Furthered by this principle of transmissible gentility
the wife's exemption gains in scope, if the wealth of her owner permits
it, until it includes exemption from debasing menial service as well as
from handicraft. As the industrial development goes on and property
becomes massed in relatively fewer hands, the conventional standard of
wealth of the upper class rises. The same tendency to exemption from
handicraft, and in the course of time from menial domestic employments,
will then assert itself as regards the other wives, if such there are, and
also as regards other servants in immediate attendance upon the person of
their master. The exemption comes more tardily the remoter the relation in
which the servant stands to the person of the master.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />