<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0010" id="link2HCH0010"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER II. ON THE THEORY OF WAR </h2>
<p>1. THE FIRST CONCEPTION OF THE "ART OF WAR" WAS MERELY THE PREPARATION OF
THE ARMED FORCES.</p>
<p>FORMERLY by the term "Art of War," or "Science of War," nothing was
understood but the totality of those branches of knowledge and those
appliances of skill occupied with material things. The pattern and
preparation and the mode of using arms, the construction of fortifications
and entrenchments, the organism of an army and the mechanism of its
movements, were the subject; these branches of knowledge and skill above
referred to, and the end and aim of them all was the establishment of an
armed force fit for use in War. All this concerned merely things belonging
to the material world and a one-sided activity only, and it was in fact
nothing but an activity advancing by gradations from the lower occupations
to a finer kind of mechanical art. The relation of all this to War itself
was very much the same as the relation of the art of the sword cutler to
the art of using the sword. The employment in the moment of danger and in
a state of constant reciprocal action of the particular energies of mind
and spirit in the direction proposed to them was not yet even mooted.</p>
<p>2. TRUE WAR FIRST APPEARS IN THE ART OF SIEGES.</p>
<p>In the art of sieges we first perceive a certain degree of guidance of the
combat, something of the action of the intellectual faculties upon the
material forces placed under their control, but generally only so far that
it very soon embodied itself again in new material forms, such as
approaches, trenches, counter-approaches, batteries, &c., and every
step which this action of the higher faculties took was marked by some
such result; it was only the thread that was required on which to string
these material inventions in order. As the intellect can hardly manifest
itself in this kind of War, except in such things, so therefore nearly all
that was necessary was done in that way.</p>
<p>3. THEN TACTICS TRIED TO FIND ITS WAY IN THE SAME DIRECTION.</p>
<p>Afterwards tactics attempted to give to the mechanism of its joints the
character of a general disposition, built upon the peculiar properties of
the instrument, which character leads indeed to the battle-field, but
instead of leading to the free activity of mind, leads to an Army made
like an automaton by its rigid formations and orders of battle, which,
movable only by the word of command, is intended to unwind its activities
like a piece of clockwork.</p>
<p>4. THE REAL CONDUCT OF WAR ONLY MADE ITS APPEARANCE INCIDENTALLY AND
INCOGNITO.</p>
<p>The conduct of War properly so called, that is, a use of the prepared
means adapted to the most special requirements, was not considered as any
suitable subject for theory, but one which should be left to natural
talents alone. By degrees, as War passed from the hand-to-hand encounters
of the middle ages into a more regular and systematic form, stray
reflections on this point also forced themselves into men's minds, but
they mostly appeared only incidentally in memoirs and narratives, and in a
certain measure incognito.</p>
<p>5. REFLECTIONS ON MILITARY EVENTS BROUGHT ABOUT THE WANT OF A THEORY.</p>
<p>As contemplation on War continually increased, and its history every day
assumed more of a critical character, the urgent want appeared of the
support of fixed maxims and rules, in order that in the controversies
naturally arising about military events the war of opinions might be
brought to some one point. This whirl of opinions, which neither revolved
on any central pivot nor according to any appreciable laws, could not but
be very distasteful to people's minds.</p>
<p>6. ENDEAVOURS TO ESTABLISH A POSITIVE THEORY.</p>
<p>There arose, therefore, an endeavour to establish maxims, rules, and even
systems for the conduct of War. By this the attainment of a positive
object was proposed, without taking into view the endless difficulties
which the conduct of War presents in that respect. The conduct of War, as
we have shown, has no definite limits in any direction, while every system
has the circumscribing nature of a synthesis, from which results an
irreconcileable opposition between such a theory and practice.</p>
<p>7. LIMITATION TO MATERIAL OBJECTS.</p>
<p>Writers on theory felt the difficulty of the subject soon enough, and
thought themselves entitled to get rid of it by directing their maxims and
systems only upon material things and a one-sided activity. Their aim was
to reach results, as in the science for the preparation for War, entirely
certain and positive, and therefore only to take into consideration that
which could be made matter of calculation.</p>
<p>8. SUPERIORITY OF NUMBERS.</p>
<p>The superiority in numbers being a material condition, it was chosen from
amongst all the factors required to produce victory, because it could be
brought under mathematical laws through combinations of time and space. It
was thought possible to leave out of sight all other circumstances, by
supposing them to be equal on each side, and therefore to neutralise one
another. This would have been very well if it had been done to gain a
preliminary knowledge of this one factor, according to its relations, but
to make it a rule for ever to consider superiority of numbers as the sole
law; to see the whole secret of the Art of War in the formula, IN A
CERTAIN TIME, AT A CERTAIN POINT, TO BRING UP SUPERIOR MASSES—was a
restriction overruled by the force of realities.</p>
<p>9. VICTUALLING OF TROOPS.</p>
<p>By one theoretical school an attempt was made to systematise another
material element also, by making the subsistence of troops, according to a
previously established organism of the Army, the supreme legislator in the
higher conduct of War. In this way certainly they arrived at definite
figures, but at figures which rested on a number of arbitrary
calculations, and which therefore could not stand the test of practical
application.</p>
<p>10. BASE.</p>
<p>An ingenious author tried to concentrate in a single conception, that of a
BASE, a whole host of objects amongst which sundry relations even with
immaterial forces found their way in as well. The list comprised the
subsistence of the troops, the keeping them complete in numbers and
equipment, the security of communications with the home country, lastly,
the security of retreat in case it became necessary; and, first of all, he
proposed to substitute this conception of a base for all these things;
then for the base itself to substitute its own length (extent); and, last
of all, to substitute the angle formed by the army with this base: all
this was done to obtain a pure geometrical result utterly useless. This
last is, in fact, unavoidable, if we reflect that none of these
substitutions could be made without violating truth and leaving out some
of the things contained in the original conception. The idea of a base is
a real necessity for strategy, and to have conceived it is meritorious;
but to make such a use of it as we have depicted is completely
inadmissible, and could not but lead to partial conclusions which have
forced these theorists into a direction opposed to common sense, namely,
to a belief in the decisive effect of the enveloping form of attack.</p>
<p>11. INTERIOR LINES.</p>
<p>As a reaction against this false direction, another geometrical principle,
that of the so-called interior lines, was then elevated to the throne.
Although this principle rests on a sound foundation, on the truth that the
combat is the only effectual means in War, still it is, just on account of
its purely geometrical nature, nothing but another case of one-sided
theory which can never gain ascendency in the real world.</p>
<p>12. ALL THESE ATTEMPTS ARE OPEN TO OBJECTION.</p>
<p>All these attempts at theory are only to be considered in their analytical
part as progress in the province of truth, but in their synthetical part,
in their precepts and rules, they are quite unserviceable.</p>
<p>They strive after determinate quantities, whilst in War all is
undetermined, and the calculation has always to be made with varying
quantities.</p>
<p>They direct the attention only upon material forces, while the whole
military action is penetrated throughout by intelligent forces and their
effects.</p>
<p>They only pay regard to activity on one side, whilst War is a constant
state of reciprocal action, the effects of which are mutual.</p>
<p>13. AS A RULE THEY EXCLUDE GENIUS.</p>
<p>All that was not attainable by such miserable philosophy, the offspring of
partial views, lay outside the precincts of science—and was the
field of genius, which RAISES ITSELF ABOVE RULES.</p>
<p>Pity the warrior who is contented to crawl about in this beggardom of
rules, which are too bad for genius, over which it can set itself
superior, over which it can perchance make merry! What genius does must be
the best of all rules, and theory cannot do better than to show how and
why it is so.</p>
<p>Pity the theory which sets itself in opposition to the mind! It cannot
repair this contradiction by any humility, and the humbler it is so much
the sooner will ridicule and contempt drive it out of real life.</p>
<p>14. THE DIFFICULTY OF THEORY AS SOON AS MORAL QUANTITIES COME INTO
CONSIDERATION.</p>
<p>Every theory becomes infinitely more difficult from the moment that it
touches on the province of moral quantities. Architecture and painting
know quite well what they are about as long as they have only to do with
matter; there is no dispute about mechanical or optical construction. But
as soon as the moral activities begin their work, as soon as moral
impressions and feelings are produced, the whole set of rules dissolves
into vague ideas.</p>
<p>The science of medicine is chiefly engaged with bodily phenomena only; its
business is with the animal organism, which, liable to perpetual change,
is never exactly the same for two moments. This makes its practice very
difficult, and places the judgment of the physician above his science; but
how much more difficult is the case if a moral effect is added, and how
much higher must we place the physician of the mind?</p>
<p>15. THE MORAL QUANTITIES MUST NOT BE EXCLUDED IN WAR.</p>
<p>But now the activity in War is never directed solely against matter; it is
always at the same time directed against the intelligent force which gives
life to this matter, and to separate the two from each other is
impossible.</p>
<p>But the intelligent forces are only visible to the inner eye, and this is
different in each person, and often different in the same person at
different times.</p>
<p>As danger is the general element in which everything moves in War, it is
also chiefly by courage, the feeling of one's own power, that the judgment
is differently influenced. It is to a certain extent the crystalline lens
through which all appearances pass before reaching the understanding.</p>
<p>And yet we cannot doubt that these things acquire a certain objective
value simply through experience.</p>
<p>Every one knows the moral effect of a surprise, of an attack in flank or
rear. Every one thinks less of the enemy's courage as soon as he turns his
back, and ventures much more in pursuit than when pursued. Every one
judges of the enemy's General by his reputed talents, by his age and
experience, and shapes his course accordingly. Every one casts a
scrutinising glance at the spirit and feeling of his own and the enemy's
troops. All these and similar effects in the province of the moral nature
of man have established themselves by experience, are perpetually
recurring, and therefore warrant our reckoning them as real quantities of
their kind. What could we do with any theory which should leave them out
of consideration?</p>
<p>Certainly experience is an indispensable title for these truths. With
psychological and philosophical sophistries no theory, no General, should
meddle.</p>
<p>16. PRINCIPAL DIFFICULTY OF A THEORY FOR THE CONDUCT OF WAR.</p>
<p>In order to comprehend clearly the difficulty of the proposition which is
contained in a theory for the conduct of War, and thence to deduce the
necessary characteristics of such a theory, we must take a closer view of
the chief particulars which make up the nature of activity in War.</p>
<p>17. FIRST SPECIALITY.—MORAL FORCES AND THEIR EFFECTS. (HOSTILE
FEELING.)</p>
<p>The first of these specialities consists in the moral forces and effects.</p>
<p>The combat is, in its origin, the expression of HOSTILE FEELING, but in
our great combats, which we call Wars, the hostile feeling frequently
resolves itself into merely a hostile VIEW, and there is usually no innate
hostile feeling residing in individual against individual. Nevertheless,
the combat never passes off without such feelings being brought into
activity. National hatred, which is seldom wanting in our Wars, is a
substitute for personal hostility in the breast of individual opposed to
individual. But where this also is wanting, and at first no animosity of
feeling subsists, a hostile feeling is kindled by the combat itself; for
an act of violence which any one commits upon us by order of his superior,
will excite in us a desire to retaliate and be revenged on him, sooner
than on the superior power at whose command the act was done. This is
human, or animal if we will; still it is so. We are very apt to regard the
combat in theory as an abstract trial of strength, without any
participation on the part of the feelings, and that is one of the thousand
errors which theorists deliberately commit, because they do not see its
consequences.</p>
<p>Besides that excitation of feelings naturally arising from the combat
itself, there are others also which do not essentially belong to it, but
which, on account of their relationship, easily unite with it—ambition,
love of power, enthusiasm of every kind, &c. &c.</p>
<p>18. THE IMPRESSIONS OF DANGER. (COURAGE.)</p>
<p>Finally, the combat begets the element of danger, in which all the
activities of War must live and move, like the bird in the air or the fish
in the water. But the influences of danger all pass into the feelings,
either directly—that is, instinctively—or through the medium
of the understanding. The effect in the first case would be a desire to
escape from the danger, and, if that cannot be done, fright and anxiety.
If this effect does not take place, then it is COURAGE, which is a
counterpoise to that instinct. Courage is, however, by no means an act of
the understanding, but likewise a feeling, like fear; the latter looks to
the physical preservation, courage to the moral preservation. Courage,
then, is a nobler instinct. But because it is so, it will not allow itself
to be used as a lifeless instrument, which produces its effects exactly
according to prescribed measure. Courage is therefore no mere counterpoise
to danger in order to neutralise the latter in its effects, but a peculiar
power in itself.</p>
<p>19. EXTENT OF THE INFLUENCE OF DANGER.</p>
<p>But to estimate exactly the influence of danger upon the principal actors
in War, we must not limit its sphere to the physical danger of the moment.
It dominates over the actor, not only by threatening him, but also by
threatening all entrusted to him, not only at the moment in which it is
actually present, but also through the imagination at all other moments,
which have a connection with the present; lastly, not only directly by
itself, but also indirectly by the responsibility which makes it bear with
tenfold weight on the mind of the chief actor. Who could advise, or
resolve upon a great battle, without feeling his mind more or less wrought
up, or perplexed by, the danger and responsibility which such a great act
of decision carries in itself? We may say that action in War, in so far as
it is real action, not a mere condition, is never out of the sphere of
danger.</p>
<p>20. OTHER POWERS OF FEELING.</p>
<p>If we look upon these affections which are excited by hostility and danger
as peculiarly belonging to War, we do not, therefore, exclude from it all
others accompanying man in his life's journey. They will also find room
here frequently enough. Certainly we may say that many a petty action of
the passions is silenced in this serious business of life; but that holds
good only in respect to those acting in a lower sphere, who, hurried on
from one state of danger and exertion to another, lose sight of the rest
of the things of life, BECOME UNUSED TO DECEIT, because it is of no avail
with death, and so attain to that soldierly simplicity of character which
has always been the best representative of the military profession. In
higher regions it is otherwise, for the higher a man's rank, the more he
must look around him; then arise interests on every side, and a manifold
activity of the passions of good and bad. Envy and generosity, pride and
humility, fierceness and tenderness, all may appear as active powers in
this great drama.</p>
<p>21. PECULIARITY OF MIND.</p>
<p>The peculiar characteristics of mind in the chief actor have, as well as
those of the feelings, a high importance. From an imaginative, flighty,
inexperienced head, and from a calm, sagacious understanding, different
things are to be expected.</p>
<p>22. FROM THE DIVERSITY IN MENTAL INDIVIDUALITIES ARISES THE DIVERSITY OF
WAYS LEADING TO THE END.</p>
<p>It is this great diversity in mental individuality, the influence of which
is to be supposed as chiefly felt in the higher ranks, because it
increases as we progress upwards, which chiefly produces the diversity of
ways leading to the end noticed by us in the first book, and which gives,
to the play of probabilities and chance, such an unequal share in
determining the course of events.</p>
<p>23. SECOND PECULIARITY.—LIVING REACTION.</p>
<p>The second peculiarity in War is the living reaction, and the reciprocal
action resulting therefrom. We do not here speak of the difficulty of
estimating that reaction, for that is included in the difficulty before
mentioned, of treating the moral powers as quantities; but of this, that
reciprocal action, by its nature, opposes anything like a regular plan.
The effect which any measure produces upon the enemy is the most distinct
of all the data which action affords; but every theory must keep to
classes (or groups) of phenomena, and can never take up the really
individual case in itself: that must everywhere be left to judgment and
talent. It is therefore natural that in a business such as War, which in
its plan—built upon general circumstances—is so often thwarted
by unexpected and singular accidents, more must generally be left to
talent; and less use can be made of a THEORETICAL GUIDE than in any other.</p>
<p>24. THIRD PECULIARITY.—UNCERTAINTY OF ALL DATA.</p>
<p>Lastly, the great uncertainty of all data in War is a peculiar difficulty,
because all action must, to a certain extent, be planned in a mere
twilight, which in addition not unfrequently—like the effect of a
fog or moonshine—gives to things exaggerated dimensions and an
unnatural appearance.</p>
<p>What this feeble light leaves indistinct to the sight talent must
discover, or must be left to chance. It is therefore again talent, or the
favour of fortune, on which reliance must be placed, for want of objective
knowledge.</p>
<p>25. POSITIVE THEORY IS IMPOSSIBLE.</p>
<p>With materials of this kind we can only say to ourselves that it is a
sheer impossibility to construct for the Art of War a theory which, like a
scaffolding, shall ensure to the chief actor an external support on all
sides. In all those cases in which he is thrown upon his talent he would
find himself away from this scaffolding of theory and in opposition to it,
and, however many-sided it might be framed, the same result would ensue of
which we spoke when we said that talent and genius act beyond the law, and
theory is in opposition to reality.</p>
<p>26. MEANS LEFT BY WHICH A THEORY IS POSSIBLE (THE DIFFICULTIES ARE NOT
EVERYWHERE EQUALLY GREAT).</p>
<p>Two means present themselves of getting out of this difficulty. In the
first place, what we have said of the nature of military action in general
does not apply in the same manner to the action of every one, whatever may
be his standing. In the lower ranks the spirit of self-sacrifice is called
more into request, but the difficulties which the understanding and
judgment meet with are infinitely less. The field of occurrences is more
confined. Ends and means are fewer in number. Data more distinct; mostly
also contained in the actually visible. But the higher we ascend the more
the difficulties increase, until in the Commander-in-Chief they reach
their climax, so that with him almost everything must be left to genius.</p>
<p>Further, according to a division of the subject in AGREEMENT WITH ITS
NATURE, the difficulties are not everywhere the same, but diminish the
more results manifest themselves in the material world, and increase the
more they pass into the moral, and become motives which influence the
will. Therefore it is easier to determine, by theoretical rules, the order
and conduct of a battle, than the use to be made of the battle itself.
Yonder physical weapons clash with each other, and although mind is not
wanting therein, matter must have its rights. But in the effects to be
produced by battles when the material results become motives, we have only
to do with the moral nature. In a word, it is easier to make a theory for
TACTICS than for STRATEGY.</p>
<p>27. THEORY MUST BE OF THE NATURE OF OBSERVATIONS NOT OF DOCTRINE.</p>
<p>The second opening for the possibility of a theory lies in the point of
view that it does not necessarily require to be a DIRECTION for action. As
a general rule, whenever an ACTIVITY is for the most part occupied with
the same objects over and over again, with the same ends and means,
although there may be trifling alterations and a corresponding number of
varieties of combination, such things are capable of becoming a subject of
study for the reasoning faculties. But such study is just the most
essential part of every THEORY, and has a peculiar title to that name. It
is an analytical investigation of the subject that leads to an exact
knowledge; and if brought to bear on the results of experience, which in
our case would be military history, to a thorough familiarity with it. The
nearer theory attains the latter object, so much the more it passes over
from the objective form of knowledge into the subjective one of skill in
action; and so much the more, therefore, it will prove itself effective
when circumstances allow of no other decision but that of personal
talents; it will show its effects in that talent itself. If theory
investigates the subjects which constitute War; if it separates more
distinctly that which at first sight seems amalgamated; if it explains
fully the properties of the means; if it shows their probable effects; if
it makes evident the nature of objects; if it brings to bear all over the
field of War the light of essentially critical investigation—then it
has fulfilled the chief duties of its province. It becomes then a guide to
him who wishes to make himself acquainted with War from books; it lights
up the whole road for him, facilitates his progress, educates his
judgment, and shields him from error.</p>
<p>If a man of expertness spends half his life in the endeavour to clear up
an obscure subject thoroughly, he will probably know more about it than a
person who seeks to master it in a short time. Theory is instituted that
each person in succession may not have to go through the same labour of
clearing the ground and toiling through his subject, but may find the
thing in order, and light admitted on it. It should educate the mind of
the future leader in War, or rather guide him in his self-instruction, but
not accompany him to the field of battle; just as a sensible tutor forms
and enlightens the opening mind of a youth without, therefore, keeping him
in leading strings all through his life.</p>
<p>If maxims and rules result of themselves from the considerations which
theory institutes, if the truth accretes itself into that form of crystal,
then theory will not oppose this natural law of the mind; it will rather,
if the arch ends in such a keystone, bring it prominently out; but so does
this, only in order to satisfy the philosophical law of reason, in order
to show distinctly the point to which the lines all converge, not in order
to form out of it an algebraical formula for use upon the battle-field;
for even these maxims and rules serve more to determine in the reflecting
mind the leading outline of its habitual movements than as landmarks
indicating to it the way in the act of execution.</p>
<p>28. BY THIS POINT OF VIEW THEORY BECOMES POSSIBLE, AND CEASES TO BE IN
CONTRADICTION TO PRACTICE.</p>
<p>Taking this point of view, there is a possibility afforded of a
satisfactory, that is, of a useful, theory of the conduct of War, never
coming into opposition with the reality, and it will only depend on
rational treatment to bring it so far into harmony with action that
between theory and practice there shall no longer be that absurd
difference which an unreasonable theory, in defiance of common sense, has
often produced, but which, just as often, narrow-mindedness and ignorance
have used as a pretext for giving way to their natural incapacity.</p>
<p>29. THEORY THEREFORE CONSIDERS THE NATURE OF ENDS AND MEANS—ENDS AND
MEANS IN TACTICS.</p>
<p>Theory has therefore to consider the nature of the means and ends.</p>
<p>In tactics the means are the disciplined armed forces which are to carry
on the contest. The object is victory. The precise definition of this
conception can be better explained hereafter in the consideration of the
combat. Here we content ourselves by denoting the retirement of the enemy
from the field of battle as the sign of victory. By means of this victory
strategy gains the object for which it appointed the combat, and which
constitutes its special signification. This signification has certainly
some influence on the nature of the victory. A victory which is intended
to weaken the enemy's armed forces is a different thing from one which is
designed only to put us in possession of a position. The signification of
a combat may therefore have a sensible influence on the preparation and
conduct of it, consequently will be also a subject of consideration in
tactics.</p>
<p>30. CIRCUMSTANCES WHICH ALWAYS ATTEND THE APPLICATION OF THE MEANS.</p>
<p>As there are certain circumstances which attend the combat throughout, and
have more or less influence upon its result, therefore these must be taken
into consideration in the application of the armed forces.</p>
<p>These circumstances are the locality of the combat (ground), the time of
day, and the weather.</p>
<p>31. LOCALITY.</p>
<p>The locality, which we prefer leaving for solution, under the head of
"Country and Ground," might, strictly speaking, be without any influence
at all if the combat took place on a completely level and uncultivated
plain.</p>
<p>In a country of steppes such a case may occur, but in the cultivated
countries of Europe it is almost an imaginary idea. Therefore a combat
between civilised nations, in which country and ground have no influence,
is hardly conceivable.</p>
<p>32. TIME OF DAY.</p>
<p>The time of day influences the combat by the difference between day and
night; but the influence naturally extends further than merely to the
limits of these divisions, as every combat has a certain duration, and
great battles last for several hours. In the preparations for a great
battle, it makes an essential difference whether it begins in the morning
or the evening. At the same time, certainly many battles may be fought in
which the question of the time of day is quite immaterial, and in the
generality of cases its influence is only trifling.</p>
<p>33. WEATHER.</p>
<p>Still more rarely has the weather any decisive influence, and it is mostly
only by fogs that it plays a part.</p>
<p>34. END AND MEANS IN STRATEGY.</p>
<p>Strategy has in the first instance only the victory, that is, the tactical
result, as a means to its object, and ultimately those things which lead
directly to peace. The application of its means to this object is at the
same time attended by circumstances which have an influence thereon more
or less.</p>
<p>35. CIRCUMSTANCES WHICH ATTEND THE APPLICATION OF THE MEANS OF STRATEGY.</p>
<p>These circumstances are country and ground, the former including the
territory and inhabitants of the whole theatre of war; next the time of
the day, and the time of the year as well; lastly, the weather,
particularly any unusual state of the same, severe frost, &c.</p>
<p>36. THESE FORM NEW MEANS.</p>
<p>By bringing these things into combination with the results of a combat,
strategy gives this result—and therefore the combat—a special
signification, places before it a particular object. But when this object
is not that which leads directly to peace, therefore a subordinate one, it
is only to be looked upon as a means; and therefore in strategy we may
look upon the results of combats or victories, in all their different
significations, as means. The conquest of a position is such a result of a
combat applied to ground. But not only are the different combats with
special objects to be considered as means, but also every higher aim which
we may have in view in the combination of battles directed on a common
object is to be regarded as a means. A winter campaign is a combination of
this kind applied to the season.</p>
<p>There remain, therefore, as objects, only those things which may be
supposed as leading DIRECTLY to peace, Theory investigates all these ends
and means according to the nature of their effects and their mutual
relations.</p>
<p>37. STRATEGY DEDUCES ONLY FROM EXPERIENCE THE ENDS AND MEANS TO BE
EXAMINED.</p>
<p>The first question is, How does strategy arrive at a complete list of
these things? If there is to be a philosophical inquiry leading to an
absolute result, it would become entangled in all those difficulties which
the logical necessity of the conduct of War and its theory exclude. It
therefore turns to experience, and directs its attention on those
combinations which military history can furnish. In this manner, no doubt,
nothing more than a limited theory can be obtained, which only suits
circumstances such as are presented in history. But this incompleteness is
unavoidable, because in any case theory must either have deduced from, or
have compared with, history what it advances with respect to things.
Besides, this incompleteness in every case is more theoretical than real.</p>
<p>One great advantage of this method is that theory cannot lose itself in
abstruse disquisitions, subtleties, and chimeras, but must always remain
practical.</p>
<p>38. HOW FAR THE ANALYSIS OF THE MEANS SHOULD BE CARRIED.</p>
<p>Another question is, How far should theory go in its analysis of the
means? Evidently only so far as the elements in a separate form present
themselves for consideration in practice. The range and effect of
different weapons is very important to tactics; their construction,
although these effects result from it, is a matter of indifference; for
the conduct of War is not making powder and cannon out of a given quantity
of charcoal, sulphur, and saltpetre, of copper and tin: the given
quantities for the conduct of War are arms in a finished state and their
effects. Strategy makes use of maps without troubling itself about
triangulations; it does not inquire how the country is subdivided into
departments and provinces, and how the people are educated and governed,
in order to attain the best military results; but it takes things as it
finds them in the community of European States, and observes where very
different conditions have a notable influence on War.</p>
<p>39. GREAT SIMPLIFICATION OF THE KNOWLEDGE REQUIRED.</p>
<p>That in this manner the number of subjects for theory is much simplified,
and the knowledge requisite for the conduct of War much reduced, is easy
to perceive. The very great mass of knowledge and appliances of skill
which minister to the action of War in general, and which are necessary
before an army fully equipped can take the field, unite in a few great
results before they are able to reach, in actual War, the final goal of
their activity; just as the streams of a country unite themselves in
rivers before they fall into the sea. Only those activities emptying
themselves directly into the sea of War have to be studied by him who is
to conduct its operations.</p>
<p>40. THIS EXPLAINS THE RAPID GROWTH OF GREAT GENERALS, AND WHY A GENERAL IS
NOT A MAN OF LEARNING.</p>
<p>This result of our considerations is in fact so necessary, any other would
have made us distrustful of their accuracy. Only thus is explained how so
often men have made their appearance with great success in War, and indeed
in the higher ranks even in supreme Command, whose pursuits had been
previously of a totally different nature; indeed how, as a rule, the most
distinguished Generals have never risen from the very learned or really
erudite class of officers, but have been mostly men who, from the
circumstances of their position, could not have attained to any great
amount of knowledge. On that account those who have considered it
necessary or even beneficial to commence the education of a future General
by instruction in all details have always been ridiculed as absurd
pedants. It would be easy to show the injurious tendency of such a course,
because the human mind is trained by the knowledge imparted to it and the
direction given to its ideas. Only what is great can make it great; the
little can only make it little, if the mind itself does not reject it as
something repugnant.</p>
<p>41. FORMER CONTRADICTIONS.</p>
<p>Because this simplicity of knowledge requisite in War was not attended to,
but that knowledge was always jumbled up with the whole impedimenta of
subordinate sciences and arts, therefore the palpable opposition to the
events of real life which resulted could not be solved otherwise than by
ascribing it all to genius, which requires no theory and for which no
theory could be prescribed.</p>
<p>42. ON THIS ACCOUNT ALL USE OF KNOWLEDGE WAS DENIED, AND EVERYTHING
ASCRIBED TO NATURAL TALENTS.</p>
<p>People with whom common sense had the upper hand felt sensible of the
immense distance remaining to be filled up between a genius of the highest
order and a learned pedant; and they became in a manner free-thinkers,
rejected all belief in theory, and affirmed the conduct of War to be a
natural function of man, which he performs more or less well according as
he has brought with him into the world more or less talent in that
direction. It cannot be denied that these were nearer to the truth than
those who placed a value on false knowledge: at the same time it may
easily be seen that such a view is itself but an exaggeration. No activity
of the human understanding is possible without a certain stock of ideas;
but these are, for the greater part at least, not innate but acquired, and
constitute his knowledge. The only question therefore is, of what kind
should these ideas be; and we think we have answered it if we say that
they should be directed on those things which man has directly to deal
with in War.</p>
<p>43. THE KNOWLEDGE MUST BE MADE SUITABLE TO THE POSITION.</p>
<p>Inside this field itself of military activity, the knowledge required must
be different according to the station of the Commander. It will be
directed on smaller and more circumscribed objects if he holds an
inferior, upon greater and more comprehensive ones if he holds a higher
situation. There are Field Marshals who would not have shone at the head
of a cavalry regiment, and vice versa.</p>
<p>44. THE KNOWLEDGE IN WAR IS VERY SIMPLE, BUT NOT, AT THE SAME TIME, VERY
EASY.</p>
<p>But although the knowledge in War is simple, that is to say directed to so
few subjects, and taking up those only in their final results, the art of
execution is not, on that account, easy. Of the difficulties to which
activity in War is subject generally, we have already spoken in the first
book; we here omit those things which can only be overcome by courage, and
maintain also that the activity of mind, is only simple, and easy in
inferior stations, but increases in difficulty with increase of rank, and
in the highest position, in that of Commander-in-Chief, is to be reckoned
among the most difficult which there is for the human mind.</p>
<p>45. OF THE NATURE OF THIS KNOWLEDGE.</p>
<p>The Commander of an Army neither requires to be a learned explorer of
history nor a publicist, but he must be well versed in the higher affairs
of State; he must know, and be able to judge correctly of traditional
tendencies, interests at stake, the immediate questions at issue, and the
characters of leading persons; he need not be a close observer of men, a
sharp dissector of human character, but he must know the character, the
feelings, the habits, the peculiar faults and inclinations of those whom
he is to command. He need not understand anything about the make of a
carriage, or the harness of a battery horse, but he must know how to
calculate exactly the march of a column, under different circumstances,
according to the time it requires. These are matters the knowledge of
which cannot be forced out by an apparatus of scientific formula and
machinery: they are only to be gained by the exercise of an accurate
judgment in the observation of things and of men, aided by a special
talent for the apprehension of both.</p>
<p>The necessary knowledge for a high position in military action is
therefore distinguished by this, that by observation, therefore by study
and reflection, it is only to be attained through a special talent which
as an intellectual instinct understands how to extract from the phenomena
of life only the essence or spirit, as bees do the honey from the flowers;
and that it is also to be gained by experience of life as well as by study
and reflection. Life will never bring forth a Newton or an Euler by its
rich teachings, but it may bring forth great calculators in War, such as
Conde' or Frederick.</p>
<p>It is therefore not necessary that, in order to vindicate the intellectual
dignity of military activity, we should resort to untruth and silly
pedantry. There never has been a great and distinguished Commander of
contracted mind, but very numerous are the instances of men who, after
serving with the greatest distinction in inferior positions, remained
below mediocrity in the highest, from insufficiency of intellectual
capacity. That even amongst those holding the post of Commander-in-Chief
there may be a difference according to the degree of their plenitude of
power is a matter of course.</p>
<p>46. SCIENCE MUST BECOME ART.</p>
<p>Now we have yet to consider one condition which is more necessary for the
knowledge of the conduct of War than for any other, which is, that it must
pass completely into the mind and almost completely cease to be something
objective. In almost all other arts and occupations of life the active
agent can make use of truths which he has only learnt once, and in the
spirit and sense of which he no longer lives, and which he extracts from
dusty books. Even truths which he has in hand and uses daily may continue
something external to himself, If the architect takes up a pen to settle
the strength of a pier by a complicated calculation, the truth found as a
result is no emanation from his own mind. He had first to find the data
with labour, and then to submit these to an operation of the mind, the
rule for which he did not discover, the necessity of which he is perhaps
at the moment only partly conscious of, but which he applies, for the most
part, as if by mechanical dexterity. But it is never so in War. The moral
reaction, the ever-changeful form of things, makes it necessary for the
chief actor to carry in himself the whole mental apparatus of his
knowledge, that anywhere and at every pulse-beat he may be capable of
giving the requisite decision from himself. Knowledge must, by this
complete assimilation with his own mind and life, be converted into real
power. This is the reason why everything seems so easy with men
distinguished in War, and why everything is ascribed to natural talent. We
say natural talent, in order thereby to distinguish it from that which is
formed and matured by observation and study.</p>
<p>We think that by these reflections we have explained the problem of a
theory of the conduct of War; and pointed out the way to its solution.</p>
<p>Of the two fields into which we have divided the conduct of War, tactics
and strategy, the theory of the latter contains unquestionably, as before
observed, the greatest difficulties, because the first is almost limited
to a circumscribed field of objects, but the latter, in the direction of
objects leading directly to peace, opens to itself an unlimited field of
possibilities. Since for the most part the Commander-in-Chief has only to
keep these objects steadily in view, therefore the part of strategy in
which he moves is also that which is particularly subject to this
difficulty.</p>
<p>Theory, therefore, especially where it comprehends the highest services,
will stop much sooner in strategy than in tactics at the simple
consideration of things, and content itself to assist the Commander to
that insight into things which, blended with his whole thought, makes his
course easier and surer, never forces him into opposition with himself in
order to obey an objective truth.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />