<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0030" id="link2HCH0030"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER XVI. ON THE SUSPENSION OF THE ACT IN WARFARE </h2>
<p>IF one considers War as an act of mutual destruction, we must of necessity
imagine both parties as making some progress; but at the same time, as
regards the existing moment, we must almost as necessarily suppose the one
party in a state of expectation, and only the other actually advancing,
for circumstances can never be actually the same on both sides, or
continue so. In time a change must ensue, from which it follows that the
present moment is more favourable to one side than the other. Now if we
suppose that both commanders have a full knowledge of this circumstance,
then the one has a motive for action, which at the same time is a motive
for the other to wait; therefore, according to this it cannot be for the
interest of both at the same time to advance, nor can waiting be for the
interest of both at the same time. This opposition of interest as regards
the object is not deduced here from the principle of general polarity, and
therefore is not in opposition to the argument in the fifth chapter of the
second book; it depends on the fact that here in reality the same thing is
at once an incentive or motive to both commanders, namely the probability
of improving or impairing their position by future action.</p>
<p>But even if we suppose the possibility of a perfect equality of
circumstances in this respect, or if we take into account that through
imperfect knowledge of their mutual position such an equality may appear
to the two Commanders to subsist, still the difference of political
objects does away with this possibility of suspension. One of the parties
must of necessity be assumed politically to be the aggressor, because no
War could take place from defensive intentions on both sides. But the
aggressor has the positive object, the defender merely a negative one. To
the first then belongs the positive action, for it is only by that means
that he can attain the positive object; therefore, in cases where both
parties are in precisely similar circumstances, the aggressor is called
upon to act by virtue of his positive object.</p>
<p>Therefore, from this point of view, a suspension in the act of Warfare,
strictly speaking, is in contradiction with the nature of the thing;
because two Armies, being two incompatible elements, should destroy one
another unremittingly, just as fire and water can never put themselves in
equilibrium, but act and react upon one another, until one quite
disappears. What would be said of two wrestlers who remained clasped round
each other for hours without making a movement. Action in War, therefore,
like that of a clock which is wound up, should go on running down in
regular motion.—But wild as is the nature of War it still wears the
chains of human weakness, and the contradiction we see here, viz., that
man seeks and creates dangers which he fears at the same time will
astonish no one.</p>
<p>If we cast a glance at military history in general, we find so much the
opposite of an incessant advance towards the aim, that STANDING STILL and
DOING NOTHING is quite plainly the NORMAL CONDITION of an Army in the
midst of War, ACTING, the EXCEPTION. This must almost raise a doubt as to
the correctness of our conception. But if military history leads to this
conclusion when viewed in the mass the latest series of campaigns redeems
our position. The War of the French Revolution shows too plainly its
reality, and only proves too clearly its necessity. In these operations,
and especially in the campaigns of Buonaparte, the conduct of War attained
to that unlimited degree of energy which we have represented as the
natural law of the element. This degree is therefore possible, and if it
is possible then it is necessary.</p>
<p>How could any one in fact justify in the eyes of reason the expenditure of
forces in War, if acting was not the object? The baker only heats his oven
if he has bread to put into it; the horse is only yoked to the carriage if
we mean to drive; why then make the enormous effort of a War if we look
for nothing else by it but like efforts on the part of the enemy?</p>
<p>So much in justification of the general principle; now as to its
modifications, as far as they lie in the nature of the thing and are
independent of special cases.</p>
<p>There are three causes to be noticed here, which appear as innate
counterpoises and prevent the over-rapid or uncontrollable movement of the
wheel-work.</p>
<p>The first, which produces a constant tendency to delay, and is thereby a
retarding principle, is the natural timidity and want of resolution in the
human mind, a kind of inertia in the moral world, but which is produced
not by attractive, but by repellent forces, that is to say, by dread of
danger and responsibility.</p>
<p>In the burning element of War, ordinary natures appear to become heavier;
the impulsion given must therefore be stronger and more frequently
repeated if the motion is to be a continuous one. The mere idea of the
object for which arms have been taken up is seldom sufficient to overcome
this resistant force, and if a warlike enterprising spirit is not at the
head, who feels himself in War in his natural element, as much as a fish
in the ocean, or if there is not the pressure from above of some great
responsibility, then standing still will be the order of the day, and
progress will be the exception.</p>
<p>The second cause is the imperfection of human perception and judgment,
which is greater in War than anywhere, because a person hardly knows
exactly his own position from one moment to another, and can only
conjecture on slight grounds that of the enemy, which is purposely
concealed; this often gives rise to the case of both parties looking upon
one and the same object as advantageous for them, while in reality the
interest of one must preponderate; thus then each may think he acts wisely
by waiting another moment, as we have already said in the fifth chapter of
the second book.</p>
<p>The third cause which catches hold, like a ratchet wheel in machinery,
from time to time producing a complete standstill, is the greater strength
of the defensive form. A may feel too weak to attack B, from which it does
not follow that B is strong enough for an attack on A. The addition of
strength, which the defensive gives is not merely lost by assuming the
offensive, but also passes to the enemy just as, figuratively expressed,
the difference of a + b and a - b is equal to 2b. Therefore it may so
happen that both parties, at one and the same time, not only feel
themselves too weak to attack, but also are so in reality.</p>
<p>Thus even in the midst of the act of War itself, anxious sagacity and the
apprehension of too great danger find vantage ground, by means of which
they can exert their power, and tame the elementary impetuosity of War.</p>
<p>However, at the same time these causes without an exaggeration of their
effect, would hardly explain the long states of inactivity which took
place in military operations, in former times, in Wars undertaken about
interests of no great importance, and in which inactivity consumed
nine-tenths of the time that the troops remained under arms. This feature
in these Wars, is to be traced principally to the influence which the
demands of the one party, and the condition, and feeling of the other,
exercised over the conduct of the operations, as has been already observed
in the chapter on the essence and object of War.</p>
<p>These things may obtain such a preponderating influence as to make of War
a half-and-half affair. A War is often nothing more than an armed
neutrality, or a menacing attitude to support negotiations or an attempt
to gain some small advantage by small exertions, and then to wait the tide
of circumstances, or a disagreeable treaty obligation, which is fulfilled
in the most niggardly way possible.</p>
<p>In all these cases in which the impulse given by interest is slight, and
the principle of hostility feeble, in which there is no desire to do much,
and also not much to dread from the enemy; in short, where no powerful
motives press and drive, cabinets will not risk much in the game; hence
this tame mode of carrying on War, in which the hostile spirit of real War
is laid in irons.</p>
<p>The more War becomes in this manner devitalised so much the more its
theory becomes destitute of the necessary firm pivots and buttresses for
its reasoning; the necessary is constantly diminishing, the accidental
constantly increasing.</p>
<p>Nevertheless in this kind of Warfare, there is also a certain shrewdness,
indeed, its action is perhaps more diversified, and more extensive than in
the other. Hazard played with realeaux of gold seems changed into a game
of commerce with groschen. And on this field, where the conduct of War
spins out the time with a number of small flourishes, with skirmishes at
outposts, half in earnest half in jest, with long dispositions which end
in nothing with positions and marches, which afterwards are designated as
skilful only because their infinitesimally small causes are lost, and
common sense can make nothing of them, here on this very field many
theorists find the real Art of War at home: in these feints, parades, half
and quarter thrusts of former Wars, they find the aim of all theory, the
supremacy of mind over matter, and modern Wars appear to them mere savage
fisticuffs, from which nothing is to be learnt, and which must be regarded
as mere retrograde steps towards barbarism. This opinion is as frivolous
as the objects to which it relates. Where great forces and great passions
are wanting, it is certainly easier for a practised dexterity to show its
game; but is then the command of great forces, not in itself a higher
exercise of the intelligent faculties? Is then that kind of conventional
sword-exercise not comprised in and belonging to the other mode of
conducting War? Does it not bear the same relation to it as the motions
upon a ship to the motion of the ship itself? Truly it can take place only
under the tacit condition that the adversary does no better. And can we
tell, how long he may choose to respect those conditions? Has not then the
French Revolution fallen upon us in the midst of the fancied security of
our old system of War, and driven us from Chalons to Moscow? And did not
Frederick the Great in like manner surprise the Austrians reposing in
their ancient habits of War, and make their monarchy tremble? Woe to the
cabinet which, with a shilly-shally policy, and a routine-ridden military
system, meets with an adversary who, like the rude element, knows no other
law than that of his intrinsic force. Every deficiency in energy and
exertion is then a weight in the scales in favour of the enemy; it is not
so easy then to change from the fencing posture into that of an athlete,
and a slight blow is often sufficient to knock down the whole.</p>
<p>The result of all the causes now adduced is, that the hostile action of a
campaign does not progress by a continuous, but by an intermittent
movement, and that, therefore, between the separate bloody acts, there is
a period of watching, during which both parties fall into the defensive,
and also that usually a higher object causes the principle of aggression
to predominate on one side, and thus leaves it in general in an advancing
position, by which then its proceedings become modified in some degree.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0031" id="link2HCH0031"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER XVII. ON THE CHARACTER OF MODERN WAR </h2>
<p>THE attention which must be paid to the character of War as it is now
made, has a great influence upon all plans, especially on strategic ones.</p>
<p>Since all methods formerly usual were upset by Buonaparte's luck and
boldness, and first-rate Powers almost wiped out at a blow; since the
Spaniards by their stubborn resistance have shown what the general arming
of a nation and insurgent measures on a great scale can effect, in spite
of weakness and porousness of individual parts; since Russia, by the
campaign of 1812 has taught us, first, that an Empire of great dimensions
is not to be conquered (which might have been easily known before),
secondly, that the probability of final success does not in all cases
diminish in the same measure as battles, capitals, and provinces are lost
(which was formerly an incontrovertible principle with all diplomatists,
and therefore made them always ready to enter at once into some bad
temporary peace), but that a nation is often strongest in the heart of its
country, if the enemy's offensive power has exhausted itself, and with
what enormous force the defensive then springs over to the offensive;
further, since Prussia (1813) has shown that sudden efforts may add to an
Army sixfold by means of the militia, and that this militia is just as fit
for service abroad as in its own country;—since all these events
have shown what an enormous factor the heart and sentiments of a Nation
may be in the product of its political and military strength, in fine,
since governments have found out all these additional aids, it is not to
be expected that they will let them lie idle in future Wars, whether it be
that danger threatens their own existence, or that restless ambition
drives them on.</p>
<p>That a War which is waged with the whole weight of the national power on
each side must be organised differently in principle to those where
everything is calculated according to the relations of standing Armies to
each other, it is easy to perceive. Standing Armies once resembled fleets,
the land force the sea force in their relations to the remainder of the
State, and from that the Art of War on shore had in it something of naval
tactics, which it has now quite lost.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0032" id="link2HCH0032"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER XVIII. TENSION AND REST </h2>
<h3> The Dynamic Law of War </h3>
<p>WE have seen in the sixteenth chapter of this book, how, in most
campaigns, much more time used to be spent in standing still and inaction
than in activity.</p>
<p>Now, although, as observed in the preceding chapter we see quite a
different character in the present form of War, still it is certain that
real action will always be interrupted more or less by long pauses; and
this leads to the necessity of our examining more closely the nature of
these two phases of War.</p>
<p>If there is a suspension of action in War, that is, if neither party wills
something positive, there is rest, and consequently equilibrium, but
certainly an equilibrium in the largest signification, in which not only
the moral and physical war-forces, but all relations and interests, come
into calculation. As soon as ever one of the two parties proposes to
himself a new positive object, and commences active steps towards it, even
if it is only by preparations, and as soon as the adversary opposes this,
there is a tension of powers; this lasts until the decision takes place—that
is, until one party either gives up his object or the other has conceded
it to him.</p>
<p>This decision—the foundation of which lies always in the combat—combinations
which are made on each side—is followed by a movement in one or
other direction.</p>
<p>When this movement has exhausted itself, either in the difficulties which
had to be mastered, in overcoming its own internal friction, or through
new resistant forces prepared by the acts of the enemy, then either a
state of rest takes place or a new tension with a decision, and then a new
movement, in most cases in the opposite direction.</p>
<p>This speculative distinction between equilibrium, tension, and motion is
more essential for practical action than may at first sight appear.</p>
<p>In a state of rest and of equilibrium a varied kind of activity may
prevail on one side that results from opportunity, and does not aim at a
great alteration. Such an activity may contain important combats—even
pitched battles—but yet it is still of quite a different nature, and
on that account generally different in its effects.</p>
<p>If a state of tension exists, the effects of the decision are always
greater partly because a greater force of will and a greater pressure of
circumstances manifest themselves therein; partly because everything has
been prepared and arranged for a great movement. The decision in such
cases resembles the effect of a mine well closed and tamped, whilst an
event in itself perhaps just as great, in a state of rest, is more or less
like a mass of powder puffed away in the open air.</p>
<p>At the same time, as a matter of course, the state of tension must be
imagined in different degrees of intensity, and it may therefore approach
gradually by many steps towards the state of rest, so that at the last
there is a very slight difference between them.</p>
<p>Now the real use which we derive from these reflections is the conclusion
that every measure which is taken during a state of tension is more
important and more prolific in results than the same measure could be in a
state of equilibrium, and that this importance increases immensely in the
highest degrees of tension.</p>
<p>The cannonade of Valmy, September 20, 1792, decided more than the battle
of Hochkirch, October 14, 1758.</p>
<p>In a tract of country which the enemy abandons to us because he cannot
defend it, we can settle ourselves differently from what we should do if
the retreat of the enemy was only made with the view to a decision under
more favourable circumstances. Again, a strategic attack in course of
execution, a faulty position, a single false march, may be decisive in its
consequence; whilst in a state of equilibrium such errors must be of a
very glaring kind, even to excite the activity of the enemy in a general
way.</p>
<p>Most bygone Wars, as we have already said, consisted, so far as regards
the greater part of the time, in this state of equilibrium, or at least in
such short tensions with long intervals between them, and weak in their
effects, that the events to which they gave rise were seldom great
successes, often they were theatrical exhibitions, got up in honour of a
royal birthday (Hochkirch), often a mere satisfying of the honour of the
arms (Kunersdorf), or the personal vanity of the commander (Freiberg).</p>
<p>That a Commander should thoroughly understand these states, that he should
have the tact to act in the spirit of them, we hold to be a great
requisite, and we have had experience in the campaign of 1806 how far it
is sometimes wanting. In that tremendous tension, when everything pressed
on towards a supreme decision, and that alone with all its consequences
should have occupied the whole soul of the Commander, measures were
proposed and even partly carried out (such as the reconnaissance towards
Franconia), which at the most might have given a kind of gentle play of
oscillation within a state of equilibrium. Over these blundering schemes
and views, absorbing the activity of the Army, the really necessary means,
which could alone save, were lost sight of.</p>
<p>But this speculative distinction which we have made is also necessary for
our further progress in the construction of our theory, because all that
we have to say on the relation of attack and defence, and on the
completion of this double-sided act, concerns the state of the crisis in
which the forces are placed during the tension and motion, and because all
the activity which can take place during the condition of equilibrium can
only be regarded and treated as a corollary; for that crisis is the real
War and this state of equilibrium only its reflection.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />