<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0353" id="link2H_4_0353"></SPAN></p>
<h2> FIRST EPILOGUE: 1813 - 20 </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0338" id="link2HCH0338"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER I </h2>
<p>Seven years had passed. The storm-tossed sea of European history had
subsided within its shores and seemed to have become calm. But the
mysterious forces that move humanity (mysterious because the laws of their
motion are unknown to us) continued to operate.</p>
<p>Though the surface of the sea of history seemed motionless, the movement
of humanity went on as unceasingly as the flow of time. Various groups of
people formed and dissolved, the coming formation and dissolution of
kingdoms and displacement of peoples was in course of preparation.</p>
<p>The sea of history was not driven spasmodically from shore to shore as
previously. It was seething in its depths. Historic figures were not borne
by the waves from one shore to another as before. They now seemed to
rotate on one spot. The historical figures at the head of armies, who
formerly reflected the movement of the masses by ordering wars, campaigns,
and battles, now reflected the restless movement by political and
diplomatic combinations, laws, and treaties.</p>
<p>The historians call this activity of the historical figures "the
reaction."</p>
<p>In dealing with this period they sternly condemn the historical personages
who, in their opinion, caused what they describe as the reaction. All the
well-known people of that period, from Alexander and Napoleon to Madame de
Stael, Photius, Schelling, Fichte, Chateaubriand, and the rest, pass
before their stern judgment seat and are acquitted or condemned according
to whether they conduced to progress or to reaction.</p>
<p>According to their accounts a reaction took place at that time in Russia
also, and the chief culprit was Alexander I, the same man who according to
them was the chief cause of the liberal movement at the commencement of
his reign, being the savior of Russia.</p>
<p>There is no one in Russian literature now, from schoolboy essayist to
learned historian, who does not throw his little stone at Alexander for
things he did wrong at this period of his reign.</p>
<p>"He ought to have acted in this way and in that way. In this case he did
well and in that case badly. He behaved admirably at the beginning of his
reign and during 1812, but acted badly by giving a constitution to Poland,
forming the Holy Alliance, entrusting power to Arakcheev, favoring
Golitsyn and mysticism, and afterwards Shishkov and Photius. He also acted
badly by concerning himself with the active army and disbanding the
Semenov regiment."</p>
<p>It would take a dozen pages to enumerate all the reproaches the historians
address to him, based on their knowledge of what is good for humanity.</p>
<p>What do these reproaches mean?</p>
<p>Do not the very actions for which the historians praise Alexander I (the
liberal attempts at the beginning of his reign, his struggle with
Napoleon, the firmness he displayed in 1812 and the campaign of 1813) flow
from the same sources—the circumstances of his birth, education, and
life—that made his personality what it was and from which the
actions for which they blame him (the Holy Alliance, the restoration of
Poland, and the reaction of 1820 and later) also flowed?</p>
<p>In what does the substance of those reproaches lie?</p>
<p>It lies in the fact that an historic character like Alexander I, standing
on the highest possible pinnacle of human power with the blinding light of
history focused upon him; a character exposed to those strongest of all
influences: the intrigues, flattery, and self-deception inseparable from
power; a character who at every moment of his life felt a responsibility
for all that was happening in Europe; and not a fictitious but a live
character who like every man had his personal habits, passions, and
impulses toward goodness, beauty, and truth—that this character—though
not lacking in virtue (the historians do not accuse him of that)—had
not the same conception of the welfare of humanity fifty years ago as a
present-day professor who from his youth upwards has been occupied with
learning: that is, with books and lectures and with taking notes from
them.</p>
<p>But even if we assume that fifty years ago Alexander I was mistaken in his
view of what was good for the people, we must inevitably assume that the
historian who judges Alexander will also after the lapse of some time turn
out to be mistaken in his view of what is good for humanity. This
assumption is all the more natural and inevitable because, watching the
movement of history, we see that every year and with each new writer,
opinion as to what is good for mankind changes; so that what once seemed
good, ten years later seems bad, and vice versa. And what is more, we find
at one and the same time quite contradictory views as to what is bad and
what is good in history: some people regard giving a constitution to
Poland and forming the Holy Alliance as praiseworthy in Alexander, while
others regard it as blameworthy.</p>
<p>The activity of Alexander or of Napoleon cannot be called useful or
harmful, for it is impossible to say for what it was useful or harmful. If
that activity displeases somebody, this is only because it does not agree
with his limited understanding of what is good. Whether the preservation
of my father's house in Moscow, or the glory of the Russian arms, or the
prosperity of the Petersburg and other universities, or the freedom of
Poland or the greatness of Russia, or the balance of power in Europe, or a
certain kind of European culture called "progress" appear to me to be good
or bad, I must admit that besides these things the action of every
historic character has other more general purposes inaccessible to me.</p>
<p>But let us assume that what is called science can harmonize all
contradictions and possesses an unchanging standard of good and bad by
which to try historic characters and events; let us say that Alexander
could have done everything differently; let us say that with guidance from
those who blame him and who profess to know the ultimate aim of the
movement of humanity, he might have arranged matters according to the
program his present accusers would have given him—of nationality,
freedom, equality, and progress (these, I think, cover the ground). Let us
assume that this program was possible and had then been formulated, and
that Alexander had acted on it. What would then have become of the
activity of all those who opposed the tendency that then prevailed in the
government—an activity that in the opinion of the historians was
good and beneficent? Their activity would not have existed: there would
have been no life, there would have been nothing.</p>
<p>If we admit that human life can be ruled by reason, the possibility of
life is destroyed.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />