<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0004" id="link2HCH0004"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Four: Education as Growth </h2>
<h3> 1. The Conditions of Growth. </h3>
<p>In directing the activities of the young, society determines its own
future in determining that of the young. Since the young at a given time
will at some later date compose the society of that period, the latter's
nature will largely turn upon the direction children's activities were
given at an earlier period. This cumulative movement of action toward a
later result is what is meant by growth.</p>
<p>The primary condition of growth is immaturity. This may seem to be a mere
truism—saying that a being can develop only in some point in which
he is undeveloped. But the prefix "im" of the word immaturity means
something positive, not a mere void or lack. It is noteworthy that the
terms "capacity" and "potentiality" have a double meaning, one sense being
negative, the other positive. Capacity may denote mere receptivity, like
the capacity of a quart measure. We may mean by potentiality a merely
dormant or quiescent state—a capacity to become something different
under external influences. But we also mean by capacity an ability, a
power; and by potentiality potency, force. Now when we say that immaturity
means the possibility of growth, we are not referring to absence of powers
which may exist at a later time; we express a force positively present—the
ability to develop.</p>
<p>Our tendency to take immaturity as mere lack, and growth as something
which fills up the gap between the immature and the mature is due to
regarding childhood comparatively, instead of intrinsically. We treat it
simply as a privation because we are measuring it by adulthood as a fixed
standard. This fixes attention upon what the child has not, and will not
have till he becomes a man. This comparative standpoint is legitimate
enough for some purposes, but if we make it final, the question arises
whether we are not guilty of an overweening presumption. Children, if they
could express themselves articulately and sincerely, would tell a
different tale; and there is excellent adult authority for the conviction
that for certain moral and intellectual purposes adults must become as
little children. The seriousness of the assumption of the negative quality
of the possibilities of immaturity is apparent when we reflect that it
sets up as an ideal and standard a static end. The fulfillment of growing
is taken to mean an accomplished growth: that is to say, an Ungrowth,
something which is no longer growing. The futility of the assumption is
seen in the fact that every adult resents the imputation of having no
further possibilities of growth; and so far as he finds that they are
closed to him mourns the fact as evidence of loss, instead of falling back
on the achieved as adequate manifestation of power. Why an unequal measure
for child and man?</p>
<p>Taken absolutely, instead of comparatively, immaturity designates a
positive force or ability,—the pouter to grow. We do not have to
draw out or educe positive activities from a child, as some educational
doctrines would have it. Where there is life, there are already eager and
impassioned activities. Growth is not something done to them; it is
something they do. The positive and constructive aspect of possibility
gives the key to understanding the two chief traits of immaturity,
dependence and plasticity.</p>
<p>(1) It sounds absurd to hear dependence spoken of as something positive,
still more absurd as a power. Yet if helplessness were all there were in
dependence, no development could ever take place. A merely impotent being
has to be carried, forever, by others. The fact that dependence is
accompanied by growth in ability, not by an ever increasing lapse into
parasitism, suggests that it is already something constructive. Being
merely sheltered by others would not promote growth. For</p>
<p>(2) it would only build a wall around impotence. With reference to the
physical world, the child is helpless. He lacks at birth and for a long
time thereafter power to make his way physically, to make his own living.
If he had to do that by himself, he would hardly survive an hour. On this
side his helplessness is almost complete. The young of the brutes are
immeasurably his superiors. He is physically weak and not able to turn the
strength which he possesses to coping with the physical environment.</p>
<p>1. The thoroughgoing character of this helplessness suggests, however,
some compensating power. The relative ability of the young of brute
animals to adapt themselves fairly well to physical conditions from an
early period suggests the fact that their life is not intimately bound up
with the life of those about them. They are compelled, so to speak, to
have physical gifts because they are lacking in social gifts. Human
infants, on the other hand, can get along with physical incapacity just
because of their social capacity. We sometimes talk and think as if they
simply happened to be physically in a social environment; as if social
forces exclusively existed in the adults who take care of them, they being
passive recipients. If it were said that children are themselves
marvelously endowed with power to enlist the cooperative attention of
others, this would be thought to be a backhanded way of saying that others
are marvelously attentive to the needs of children. But observation shows
that children are gifted with an equipment of the first order for social
intercourse. Few grown-up persons retain all of the flexible and sensitive
ability of children to vibrate sympathetically with the attitudes and
doings of those about them. Inattention to physical things (going with
incapacity to control them) is accompanied by a corresponding
intensification of interest and attention as to the doings of people. The
native mechanism of the child and his impulses all tend to facile social
responsiveness. The statement that children, before adolescence, are
egotistically self-centered, even if it were true, would not contradict
the truth of this statement. It would simply indicate that their social
responsiveness is employed on their own behalf, not that it does not
exist. But the statement is not true as matter of fact. The facts which
are cited in support of the alleged pure egoism of children really show
the intensity and directness with which they go to their mark. If the ends
which form the mark seem narrow and selfish to adults, it is only because
adults (by means of a similar engrossment in their day) have mastered
these ends, which have consequently ceased to interest them. Most of the
remainder of children's alleged native egoism is simply an egoism which
runs counter to an adult's egoism. To a grown-up person who is too
absorbed in his own affairs to take an interest in children's affairs,
children doubtless seem unreasonably engrossed in their own affairs.</p>
<p>From a social standpoint, dependence denotes a power rather than a
weakness; it involves interdependence. There is always a danger that
increased personal independence will decrease the social capacity of an
individual. In making him more self-reliant, it may make him more
self-sufficient; it may lead to aloofness and indifference. It often makes
an individual so insensitive in his relations to others as to develop an
illusion of being really able to stand and act alone—an unnamed form
of insanity which is responsible for a large part of the remediable
suffering of the world.</p>
<p>2. The specific adaptability of an immature creature for growth
constitutes his plasticity. This is something quite different from the
plasticity of putty or wax. It is not a capacity to take on change of form
in accord with external pressure. It lies near the pliable elasticity by
which some persons take on the color of their surroundings while retaining
their own bent. But it is something deeper than this. It is essentially
the ability to learn from experience; the power to retain from one
experience something which is of avail in coping with the difficulties of
a later situation. This means power to modify actions on the basis of the
results of prior experiences, the power to develop dispositions. Without
it, the acquisition of habits is impossible.</p>
<p>It is a familiar fact that the young of the higher animals, and especially
the human young, have to learn to utilize their instinctive reactions. The
human being is born with a greater number of instinctive tendencies than
other animals. But the instincts of the lower animals perfect themselves
for appropriate action at an early period after birth, while most of those
of the human infant are of little account just as they stand. An original
specialized power of adjustment secures immediate efficiency, but, like a
railway ticket, it is good for one route only. A being who, in order to
use his eyes, ears, hands, and legs, has to experiment in making varied
combinations of their reactions, achieves a control that is flexible and
varied. A chick, for example, pecks accurately at a bit of food in a few
hours after hatching. This means that definite coordinations of activities
of the eyes in seeing and of the body and head in striking are perfected
in a few trials. An infant requires about six months to be able to gauge
with approximate accuracy the action in reaching which will coordinate
with his visual activities; to be able, that is, to tell whether he can
reach a seen object and just how to execute the reaching. As a result, the
chick is limited by the relative perfection of its original endowment. The
infant has the advantage of the multitude of instinctive tentative
reactions and of the experiences that accompany them, even though he is at
a temporary disadvantage because they cross one another. In learning an
action, instead of having it given ready-made, one of necessity learns to
vary its factors, to make varied combinations of them, according to change
of circumstances. A possibility of continuing progress is opened up by the
fact that in learning one act, methods are developed good for use in other
situations. Still more important is the fact that the human being acquires
a habit of learning. He learns to learn.</p>
<p>The importance for human life of the two facts of dependence and variable
control has been summed up in the doctrine of the significance of
prolonged infancy. 1 This prolongation is significant from the standpoint
of the adult members of the group as well as from that of the young. The
presence of dependent and learning beings is a stimulus to nurture and
affection. The need for constant continued care was probably a chief means
in transforming temporary cohabitations into permanent unions. It
certainly was a chief influence in forming habits of affectionate and
sympathetic watchfulness; that constructive interest in the well-being of
others which is essential to associated life. Intellectually, this moral
development meant the introduction of many new objects of attention; it
stimulated foresight and planning for the future. Thus there is a
reciprocal influence. Increasing complexity of social life requires a
longer period of infancy in which to acquire the needed powers; this
prolongation of dependence means prolongation of plasticity, or power of
acquiring variable and novel modes of control. Hence it provides a further
push to social progress.</p>
<p>2. Habits as Expressions of Growth. We have already noted that plasticity
is the capacity to retain and carry over from prior experience factors
which modify subsequent activities. This signifies the capacity to acquire
habits, or develop definite dispositions. We have now to consider the
salient features of habits. In the first place, a habit is a form of
executive skill, of efficiency in doing. A habit means an ability to use
natural conditions as means to ends. It is an active control of the
environment through control of the organs of action. We are perhaps apt to
emphasize the control of the body at the expense of control of the
environment. We think of walking, talking, playing the piano, the
specialized skills characteristic of the etcher, the surgeon, the
bridge-builder, as if they were simply ease, deftness, and accuracy on the
part of the organism. They are that, of course; but the measure of the
value of these qualities lies in the economical and effective control of
the environment which they secure. To be able to walk is to have certain
properties of nature at our disposal—and so with all other habits.</p>
<p>Education is not infrequently defined as consisting in the acquisition of
those habits that effect an adjustment of an individual and his
environment. The definition expresses an essential phase of growth. But it
is essential that adjustment be understood in its active sense of control
of means for achieving ends. If we think of a habit simply as a change
wrought in the organism, ignoring the fact that this change consists in
ability to effect subsequent changes in the environment, we shall be led
to think of "adjustment" as a conformity to environment as wax conforms to
the seal which impresses it. The environment is thought of as something
fixed, providing in its fixity the end and standard of changes taking
place in the organism; adjustment is just fitting ourselves to this fixity
of external conditions. 2 Habit as habituation is indeed something
relatively passive; we get used to our surroundings—to our clothing,
our shoes, and gloves; to the atmosphere as long as it is fairly equable;
to our daily associates, etc. Conformity to the environment, a change
wrought in the organism without reference to ability to modify
surroundings, is a marked trait of such habituations. Aside from the fact
that we are not entitled to carry over the traits of such adjustments
(which might well be called accommodations, to mark them off from active
adjustments) into habits of active use of our surroundings, two features
of habituations are worth notice. In the first place, we get used to
things by first using them.</p>
<p>Consider getting used to a strange city. At first, there is excessive
stimulation and excessive and ill-adapted response. Gradually certain
stimuli are selected because of their relevancy, and others are degraded.
We can say either that we do not respond to them any longer, or more truly
that we have effected a persistent response to them—an equilibrium
of adjustment. This means, in the second place, that this enduring
adjustment supplies the background upon which are made specific
adjustments, as occasion arises. We are never interested in changing the
whole environment; there is much that we take for granted and accept just
as it already is. Upon this background our activities focus at certain
points in an endeavor to introduce needed changes. Habituation is thus our
adjustment to an environment which at the time we are not concerned with
modifying, and which supplies a leverage to our active habits. Adaptation,
in fine, is quite as much adaptation of the environment to our own
activities as of our activities to the environment. A savage tribe manages
to live on a desert plain. It adapts itself. But its adaptation involves a
maximum of accepting, tolerating, putting up with things as they are, a
maximum of passive acquiescence, and a minimum of active control, of
subjection to use. A civilized people enters upon the scene. It also
adapts itself. It introduces irrigation; it searches the world for plants
and animals that will flourish under such conditions; it improves, by
careful selection, those which are growing there. As a consequence, the
wilderness blossoms as a rose. The savage is merely habituated; the
civilized man has habits which transform the environment.</p>
<p>The significance of habit is not exhausted, however, in its executive and
motor phase. It means formation of intellectual and emotional disposition
as well as an increase in ease, economy, and efficiency of action. Any
habit marks an inclination—an active preference and choice for the
conditions involved in its exercise. A habit does not wait, Micawber-like,
for a stimulus to turn up so that it may get busy; it actively seeks for
occasions to pass into full operation. If its expression is unduly
blocked, inclination shows itself in uneasiness and intense craving. A
habit also marks an intellectual disposition. Where there is a habit,
there is acquaintance with the materials and equipment to which action is
applied. There is a definite way of understanding the situations in which
the habit operates. Modes of thought, of observation and reflection, enter
as forms of skill and of desire into the habits that make a man an
engineer, an architect, a physician, or a merchant. In unskilled forms of
labor, the intellectual factors are at minimum precisely because the
habits involved are not of a high grade. But there are habits of judging
and reasoning as truly as of handling a tool, painting a picture, or
conducting an experiment. Such statements are, however, understatements.
The habits of mind involved in habits of the eye and hand supply the
latter with their significance. Above all, the intellectual element in a
habit fixes the relation of the habit to varied and elastic use, and hence
to continued growth. We speak of fixed habits. Well, the phrase may mean
powers so well established that their possessor always has them as
resources when needed. But the phrase is also used to mean ruts, routine
ways, with loss of freshness, open-mindedness, and originality. Fixity of
habit may mean that something has a fixed hold upon us, instead of our
having a free hold upon things. This fact explains two points in a common
notion about habits: their identification with mechanical and external
modes of action to the neglect of mental and moral attitudes, and the
tendency to give them a bad meaning, an identification with "bad habits."
Many a person would feel surprised to have his aptitude in his chosen
profession called a habit, and would naturally think of his use of
tobacco, liquor, or profane language as typical of the meaning of habit. A
habit is to him something which has a hold on him, something not easily
thrown off even though judgment condemn it.</p>
<p>Habits reduce themselves to routine ways of acting, or degenerate into
ways of action to which we are enslaved just in the degree in which
intelligence is disconnected from them. Routine habits are unthinking
habits: "bad" habits are habits so severed from reason that they are
opposed to the conclusions of conscious deliberation and decision. As we
have seen, the acquiring of habits is due to an original plasticity of our
natures: to our ability to vary responses till we find an appropriate and
efficient way of acting. Routine habits, and habits that possess us
instead of our possessing them, are habits which put an end to plasticity.
They mark the close of power to vary. There can be no doubt of the
tendency of organic plasticity, of the physiological basis, to lessen with
growing years. The instinctively mobile and eagerly varying action of
childhood, the love of new stimuli and new developments, too easily passes
into a "settling down," which means aversion to change and a resting on
past achievements. Only an environment which secures the full use of
intelligence in the process of forming habits can counteract this
tendency. Of course, the same hardening of the organic conditions affects
the physiological structures which are involved in thinking. But this fact
only indicates the need of persistent care to see to it that the function
of intelligence is invoked to its maximum possibility. The short-sighted
method which falls back on mechanical routine and repetition to secure
external efficiency of habit, motor skill without accompanying thought,
marks a deliberate closing in of surroundings upon growth.</p>
<p>3. The Educational Bearings of the Conception of Development. We have had
so far but little to say in this chapter about education. We have been
occupied with the conditions and implications of growth. If our
conclusions are justified, they carry with them, however, definite
educational consequences. When it is said that education is development,
everything depends upon how development is conceived. Our net conclusion
is that life is development, and that developing, growing, is life.
Translated into its educational equivalents, that means (i) that the
educational process has no end beyond itself; it is its own end; and that
(ii) the educational process is one of continual reorganizing,
reconstructing, transforming.</p>
<p>1. Development when it is interpreted in comparative terms, that is, with
respect to the special traits of child and adult life, means the direction
of power into special channels: the formation of habits involving
executive skill, definiteness of interest, and specific objects of
observation and thought. But the comparative view is not final. The child
has specific powers; to ignore that fact is to stunt or distort the organs
upon which his growth depends. The adult uses his powers to transform his
environment, thereby occasioning new stimuli which redirect his powers and
keep them developing. Ignoring this fact means arrested development, a
passive accommodation. Normal child and normal adult alike, in other
words, are engaged in growing. The difference between them is not the
difference between growth and no growth, but between the modes of growth
appropriate to different conditions. With respect to the development of
powers devoted to coping with specific scientific and economic problems we
may say the child should be growing in manhood. With respect to
sympathetic curiosity, unbiased responsiveness, and openness of mind, we
may say that the adult should be growing in childlikeness. One statement
is as true as the other.</p>
<p>Three ideas which have been criticized, namely, the merely privative
nature of immaturity, static adjustment to a fixed environment, and
rigidity of habit, are all connected with a false idea of growth or
development,—that it is a movement toward a fixed goal. Growth is
regarded as having an end, instead of being an end. The educational
counterparts of the three fallacious ideas are first, failure to take
account of the instinctive or native powers of the young; secondly,
failure to develop initiative in coping with novel situations; thirdly, an
undue emphasis upon drill and other devices which secure automatic skill
at the expense of personal perception. In all cases, the adult environment
is accepted as a standard for the child. He is to be brought up to it.</p>
<p>Natural instincts are either disregarded or treated as nuisances—as
obnoxious traits to be suppressed, or at all events to be brought into
conformity with external standards. Since conformity is the aim, what is
distinctively individual in a young person is brushed aside, or regarded
as a source of mischief or anarchy. Conformity is made equivalent to
uniformity. Consequently, there are induced lack of interest in the novel,
aversion to progress, and dread of the uncertain and the unknown. Since
the end of growth is outside of and beyond the process of growing,
external agents have to be resorted to to induce movement toward it.
Whenever a method of education is stigmatized as mechanical, we may be
sure that external pressure is brought to bear to reach an external end.</p>
<p>2. Since in reality there is nothing to which growth is relative save more
growth, there is nothing to which education is subordinate save more
education. It is a commonplace to say that education should not cease when
one leaves school. The point of this commonplace is that the purpose of
school education is to insure the continuance of education by organizing
the powers that insure growth. The inclination to learn from life itself
and to make the conditions of life such that all will learn in the process
of living is the finest product of schooling.</p>
<p>When we abandon the attempt to define immaturity by means of fixed
comparison with adult accomplishments, we are compelled to give up
thinking of it as denoting lack of desired traits. Abandoning this notion,
we are also forced to surrender our habit of thinking of instruction as a
method of supplying this lack by pouring knowledge into a mental and moral
hole which awaits filling. Since life means growth, a living creature
lives as truly and positively at one stage as at another, with the same
intrinsic fullness and the same absolute claims. Hence education means the
enterprise of supplying the conditions which insure growth, or adequacy of
life, irrespective of age. We first look with impatience upon immaturity,
regarding it as something to be got over as rapidly as possible. Then the
adult formed by such educative methods looks back with impatient regret
upon childhood and youth as a scene of lost opportunities and wasted
powers. This ironical situation will endure till it is recognized that
living has its own intrinsic quality and that the business of education is
with that quality. Realization that life is growth protects us from that
so-called idealizing of childhood which in effect is nothing but lazy
indulgence. Life is not to be identified with every superficial act and
interest. Even though it is not always easy to tell whether what appears
to be mere surface fooling is a sign of some nascent as yet untrained
power, we must remember that manifestations are not to be accepted as ends
in themselves. They are signs of possible growth. They are to be turned
into means of development, of carrying power forward, not indulged or
cultivated for their own sake. Excessive attention to surface phenomena
(even in the way of rebuke as well as of encouragement) may lead to their
fixation and thus to arrested development. What impulses are moving
toward, not what they have been, is the important thing for parent and
teacher. The true principle of respect for immaturity cannot be better put
than in the words of Emerson: "Respect the child. Be not too much his
parent. Trespass not on his solitude. But I hear the outcry which replies
to this suggestion: Would you verily throw up the reins of public and
private discipline; would you leave the young child to the mad career of
his own passions and whimsies, and call this anarchy a respect for the
child's nature? I answer,—Respect the child, respect him to the end,
but also respect yourself.... The two points in a boy's training are, to
keep his naturel and train off all but that; to keep his naturel, but stop
off his uproar, fooling, and horseplay; keep his nature and arm it with
knowledge in the very direction in which it points." And as Emerson goes
on to show this reverence for childhood and youth instead of opening up an
easy and easy-going path to the instructors, "involves at once, immense
claims on the time, the thought, on the life of the teacher. It requires
time, use, insight, event, all the great lessons and assistances of God;
and only to think of using it implies character and profoundness."</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM4" id="link2H_SUMM4"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. Power to grow depends upon need for others and plasticity. </h2>
<p>Both of these conditions are at their height in childhood and youth.
Plasticity or the power to learn from experience means the formation of
habits. Habits give control over the environment, power to utilize it for
human purposes. Habits take the form both of habituation, or a general and
persistent balance of organic activities with the surroundings, and of
active capacities to readjust activity to meet new conditions. The former
furnishes the background of growth; the latter constitute growing. Active
habits involve thought, invention, and initiative in applying capacities
to new aims. They are opposed to routine which marks an arrest of growth.
Since growth is the characteristic of life, education is all one with
growing; it has no end beyond itself. The criterion of the value of school
education is the extent in which it creates a desire for continued growth
and supplies means for making the desire effective in fact.</p>
<p>1 Intimations of its significance are found in a number of writers, but
John Fiske, in his Excursions of an Evolutionist, is accredited with its
first systematic exposition.</p>
<p>2 This conception is, of course, a logical correlate of the conceptions of
the external relation of stimulus and response, considered in the last
chapter, and of the negative conceptions of immaturity and plasticity
noted in this chapter.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />