<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0018" id="link2HCH0018"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Eighteen: Educational Values </h2>
<p>The considerations involved in a discussion of educational values have
already been brought out in the discussion of aims and interests.</p>
<p>The specific values usually discussed in educational theories coincide
with aims which are usually urged. They are such things as utility,
culture, information, preparation for social efficiency, mental discipline
or power, and so on. The aspect of these aims in virtue of which they are
valuable has been treated in our analysis of the nature of interest, and
there is no difference between speaking of art as an interest or concern
and referring to it as a value. It happens, however, that discussion of
values has usually been centered about a consideration of the various ends
subserved by specific subjects of the curriculum. It has been a part of
the attempt to justify those subjects by pointing out the significant
contributions to life accruing from their study. An explicit discussion of
educational values thus affords an opportunity for reviewing the prior
discussion of aims and interests on one hand and of the curriculum on the
other, by bringing them into connection with one another.</p>
<p>1. The Nature of Realization or Appreciation. Much of our experience is
indirect; it is dependent upon signs which intervene between the things
and ourselves, signs which stand for or represent the former. It is one
thing to have been engaged in war, to have shared its dangers and
hardships; it is another thing to hear or read about it. All language, all
symbols, are implements of an indirect experience; in technical language
the experience which is procured by their means is "mediated." It stands
in contrast with an immediate, direct experience, something in which we
take part vitally and at first hand, instead of through the intervention
of representative media. As we have seen, the scope of personal, vitally
direct experience is very limited. If it were not for the intervention of
agencies for representing absent and distant affairs, our experience would
remain almost on the level of that of the brutes. Every step from savagery
to civilization is dependent upon the invention of media which enlarge the
range of purely immediate experience and give it deepened as well as wider
meaning by connecting it with things which can only be signified or
symbolized. It is doubtless this fact which is the cause of the
disposition to identify an uncultivated person with an illiterate person—so
dependent are we on letters for effective representative or indirect
experience.</p>
<p>At the same time (as we have also had repeated occasion to see) there is
always a danger that symbols will not be truly representative; danger that
instead of really calling up the absent and remote in a way to make it
enter a present experience, the linguistic media of representation will
become an end in themselves. Formal education is peculiarly exposed to
this danger, with the result that when literacy supervenes, mere
bookishness, what is popularly termed the academic, too often comes with
it. In colloquial speech, the phrase a "realizing sense" is used to
express the urgency, warmth, and intimacy of a direct experience in
contrast with the remote, pallid, and coldly detached quality of a
representative experience. The terms "mental realization" and
"appreciation" (or genuine appreciation) are more elaborate names for the
realizing sense of a thing. It is not possible to define these ideas
except by synonyms, like "coming home to one" "really taking it in," etc.,
for the only way to appreciate what is meant by a direct experience of a
thing is by having it. But it is the difference between reading a
technical description of a picture, and seeing it; or between just seeing
it and being moved by it; between learning mathematical equations about
light and being carried away by some peculiarly glorious illumination of a
misty landscape. We are thus met by the danger of the tendency of
technique and other purely representative forms to encroach upon the
sphere of direct appreciations; in other words, the tendency to assume
that pupils have a foundation of direct realization of situations
sufficient for the superstructure of representative experience erected by
formulated school studies. This is not simply a matter of quantity or
bulk. Sufficient direct experience is even more a matter of quality; it
must be of a sort to connect readily and fruitfully with the symbolic
material of instruction. Before teaching can safely enter upon conveying
facts and ideas through the media of signs, schooling must provide genuine
situations in which personal participation brings home the import of the
material and the problems which it conveys. From the standpoint of the
pupil, the resulting experiences are worth while on their own account;
from the standpoint of the teacher they are also means of supplying
subject matter required for understanding instruction involving signs, and
of evoking attitudes of open-mindedness and concern as to the material
symbolically conveyed.</p>
<p>In the outline given of the theory of educative subject matter, the demand
for this background of realization or appreciation is met by the provision
made for play and active occupations embodying typical situations. Nothing
need be added to what has already been said except to point out that while
the discussion dealt explicitly with the subject matter of primary
education, where the demand for the available background of direct
experience is most obvious, the principle applies to the primary or
elementary phase of every subject. The first and basic function of
laboratory work, for example, in a high school or college in a new field,
is to familiarize the student at first hand with a certain range of facts
and problems—to give him a "feeling" for them. Getting command of
technique and of methods of reaching and testing generalizations is at
first secondary to getting appreciation. As regards the primary school
activities, it is to be borne in mind that the fundamental intent is not
to amuse nor to convey information with a minimum of vexation nor yet to
acquire skill,—though these results may accrue as by-products,—but
to enlarge and enrich the scope of experience, and to keep alert and
effective the interest in intellectual progress.</p>
<p>The rubric of appreciation supplies an appropriate head for bringing out
three further principles: the nature of effective or real (as distinct
from nominal) standards of value; the place of the imagination in
appreciative realizations; and the place of the fine arts in the course of
study.</p>
<p>1. The nature of standards of valuation. Every adult has acquired, in the
course of his prior experience and education, certain measures of the
worth of various sorts of experience. He has learned to look upon
qualities like honesty, amiability, perseverance, loyalty, as moral goods;
upon certain classics of literature, painting, music, as aesthetic values,
and so on. Not only this, but he has learned certain rules for these
values—the golden rule in morals; harmony, balance, etc.,
proportionate distribution in aesthetic goods; definition, clarity, system
in intellectual accomplishments. These principles are so important as
standards of judging the worth of new experiences that parents and
instructors are always tending to teach them directly to the young. They
overlook the danger that standards so taught will be merely symbolic; that
is, largely conventional and verbal. In reality, working as distinct from
professed standards depend upon what an individual has himself
specifically appreciated to be deeply significant in concrete situations.
An individual may have learned that certain characteristics are
conventionally esteemed in music; he may be able to converse with some
correctness about classic music; he may even honestly believe that these
traits constitute his own musical standards. But if in his own past
experience, what he has been most accustomed to and has most enjoyed is
ragtime, his active or working measures of valuation are fixed on the
ragtime level. The appeal actually made to him in his own personal
realization fixes his attitude much more deeply than what he has been
taught as the proper thing to say; his habitual disposition thus fixed
forms his real "norm" of valuation in subsequent musical experiences.</p>
<p>Probably few would deny this statement as to musical taste. But it applies
equally well in judgments of moral and intellectual worth. A youth who has
had repeated experience of the full meaning of the value of kindliness
toward others built into his disposition has a measure of the worth of
generous treatment of others. Without this vital appreciation, the duty
and virtue of unselfishness impressed upon him by others as a standard
remains purely a matter of symbols which he cannot adequately translate
into realities. His "knowledge" is second-handed; it is only a knowledge
that others prize unselfishness as an excellence, and esteem him in the
degree in which he exhibits it. Thus there grows up a split between a
person's professed standards and his actual ones. A person may be aware of
the results of this struggle between his inclinations and his theoretical
opinions; he suffers from the conflict between doing what is really dear
to him and what he has learned will win the approval of others. But of the
split itself he is unaware; the result is a kind of unconscious hypocrisy,
an instability of disposition. In similar fashion, a pupil who has worked
through some confused intellectual situation and fought his way to
clearing up obscurities in a definite outcome, appreciates the value of
clarity and definition. He has a standard which can be depended upon. He
may be trained externally to go through certain motions of analysis and
division of subject matter and may acquire information about the value of
these processes as standard logical functions, but unless it somehow comes
home to him at some point as an appreciation of his own, the significance
of the logical norms—so-called—remains as much an external
piece of information as, say, the names of rivers in China. He may be able
to recite, but the recital is a mechanical rehearsal.</p>
<p>It is, then, a serious mistake to regard appreciation as if it were
confined to such things as literature and pictures and music. Its scope is
as comprehensive as the work of education itself. The formation of habits
is a purely mechanical thing unless habits are also tastes—habitual
modes of preference and esteem, an effective sense of excellence. There
are adequate grounds for asserting that the premium so often put in
schools upon external "discipline," and upon marks and rewards, upon
promotion and keeping back, are the obverse of the lack of attention given
to life situations in which the meaning of facts, ideas, principles, and
problems is vitally brought home.</p>
<p>2. Appreciative realizations are to be distinguished from symbolic or
representative experiences. They are not to be distinguished from the work
of the intellect or understanding. Only a personal response involving
imagination can possibly procure realization even of pure "facts." The
imagination is the medium of appreciation in every field. The engagement
of the imagination is the only thing that makes any activity more than
mechanical. Unfortunately, it is too customary to identify the imaginative
with the imaginary, rather than with a warm and intimate taking in of the
full scope of a situation. This leads to an exaggerated estimate of fairy
tales, myths, fanciful symbols, verse, and something labeled "Fine Art,"
as agencies for developing imagination and appreciation; and, by
neglecting imaginative vision in other matters, leads to methods which
reduce much instruction to an unimaginative acquiring of specialized skill
and amassing of a load of information. Theory, and—to some extent—practice,
have advanced far enough to recognize that play-activity is an imaginative
enterprise. But it is still usual to regard this activity as a specially
marked-off stage of childish growth, and to overlook the fact that the
difference between play and what is regarded as serious employment should
be not a difference between the presence and absence of imagination, but a
difference in the materials with which imagination is occupied. The result
is an unwholesome exaggeration of the phantastic and "unreal" phases of
childish play and a deadly reduction of serious occupation to a routine
efficiency prized simply for its external tangible results. Achievement
comes to denote the sort of thing that a well-planned machine can do
better than a human being can, and the main effect of education, the
achieving of a life of rich significance, drops by the wayside. Meantime
mind-wandering and wayward fancy are nothing but the unsuppressible
imagination cut loose from concern with what is done.</p>
<p>An adequate recognition of the play of imagination as the medium of
realization of every kind of thing which lies beyond the scope of direct
physical response is the sole way of escape from mechanical methods in
teaching. The emphasis put in this book, in accord with many tendencies in
contemporary education, upon activity, will be misleading if it is not
recognized that the imagination is as much a normal and integral part of
human activity as is muscular movement. The educative value of manual
activities and of laboratory exercises, as well as of play, depends upon
the extent in which they aid in bringing about a sensing of the meaning of
what is going on. In effect, if not in name, they are dramatizations.
Their utilitarian value in forming habits of skill to be used for tangible
results is important, but not when isolated from the appreciative side.
Were it not for the accompanying play of imagination, there would be no
road from a direct activity to representative knowledge; for it is by
imagination that symbols are translated over into a direct meaning and
integrated with a narrower activity so as to expand and enrich it. When
the representative creative imagination is made merely literary and
mythological, symbols are rendered mere means of directing physical
reactions of the organs of speech.</p>
<p>3. In the account previously given nothing was explicitly said about the
place of literature and the fine arts in the course of study. The omission
at that point was intentional. At the outset, there is no sharp
demarcation of useful, or industrial, arts and fine arts. The activities
mentioned in Chapter XV contain within themselves the factors later
discriminated into fine and useful arts. As engaging the emotions and the
imagination, they have the qualities which give the fine arts their
quality. As demanding method or skill, the adaptation of tools to
materials with constantly increasing perfection, they involve the element
of technique indispensable to artistic production. From the standpoint of
product, or the work of art, they are naturally defective, though even in
this respect when they comprise genuine appreciation they often have a
rudimentary charm. As experiences they have both an artistic and an
esthetic quality. When they emerge into activities which are tested by
their product and when the socially serviceable value of the product is
emphasized, they pass into useful or industrial arts. When they develop in
the direction of an enhanced appreciation of the immediate qualities which
appeal to taste, they grow into fine arts.</p>
<p>In one of its meanings, appreciation is opposed to depreciation. It
denotes an enlarged, an intensified prizing, not merely a prizing, much
less—like depreciation—a lowered and degraded prizing. This
enhancement of the qualities which make any ordinary experience appealing,
appropriable—capable of full assimilation—and enjoyable,
constitutes the prime function of literature, music, drawing, painting,
etc., in education. They are not the exclusive agencies of appreciation in
the most general sense of that word; but they are the chief agencies of an
intensified, enhanced appreciation. As such, they are not only
intrinsically and directly enjoyable, but they serve a purpose beyond
themselves. They have the office, in increased degree, of all appreciation
in fixing taste, in forming standards for the worth of later experiences.
They arouse discontent with conditions which fall below their measure;
they create a demand for surroundings coming up to their own level. They
reveal a depth and range of meaning in experiences which otherwise might
be mediocre and trivial. They supply, that is, organs of vision. Moreover,
in their fullness they represent the concentration and consummation of
elements of good which are otherwise scattered and incomplete. They select
and focus the elements of enjoyable worth which make any experience
directly enjoyable. They are not luxuries of education, but emphatic
expressions of that which makes any education worth while.</p>
<p>2. The Valuation of Studies. The theory of educational values involves not
only an account of the nature of appreciation as fixing the measure of
subsequent valuations, but an account of the specific directions in which
these valuations occur. To value means primarily to prize, to esteem; but
secondarily it means to apprise, to estimate. It means, that is, the act
of cherishing something, holding it dear, and also the act of passing
judgment upon the nature and amount of its value as compared with
something else. To value in the latter sense is to valuate or evaluate.
The distinction coincides with that sometimes made between intrinsic and
instrumental values. Intrinsic values are not objects of judgment, they
cannot (as intrinsic) be compared, or regarded as greater and less, better
or worse. They are invaluable; and if a thing is invaluable, it is neither
more nor less so than any other invaluable. But occasions present
themselves when it is necessary to choose, when we must let one thing go
in order to take another. This establishes an order of preference, a
greater and less, better and worse. Things judged or passed upon have to
be estimated in relation to some third thing, some further end. With
respect to that, they are means, or instrumental values.</p>
<p>We may imagine a man who at one time thoroughly enjoys converse with his
friends, at another the hearing of a symphony; at another the eating of
his meals; at another the reading of a book; at another the earning of
money, and so on. As an appreciative realization, each of these is an
intrinsic value. It occupies a particular place in life; it serves its own
end, which cannot be supplied by a substitute. There is no question of
comparative value, and hence none of valuation. Each is the specific good
which it is, and that is all that can be said. In its own place, none is a
means to anything beyond itself. But there may arise a situation in which
they compete or conflict, in which a choice has to be made. Now comparison
comes in. Since a choice has to be made, we want to know the respective
claims of each competitor. What is to be said for it? What does it offer
in comparison with, as balanced over against, some other possibility?
Raising these questions means that a particular good is no longer an end
in itself, an intrinsic good. For if it were, its claims would be
incomparable, imperative. The question is now as to its status as a means
of realizing something else, which is then the invaluable of that
situation. If a man has just eaten, or if he is well fed generally and the
opportunity to hear music is a rarity, he will probably prefer the music
to eating. In the given situation that will render the greater
contribution. If he is starving, or if he is satiated with music for the
time being, he will naturally judge food to have the greater worth. In the
abstract or at large, apart from the needs of a particular situation in
which choice has to be made, there is no such thing as degrees or order of
value. Certain conclusions follow with respect to educational values. We
cannot establish a hierarchy of values among studies. It is futile to
attempt to arrange them in an order, beginning with one having least worth
and going on to that of maximum value. In so far as any study has a unique
or irreplaceable function in experience, in so far as it marks a
characteristic enrichment of life, its worth is intrinsic or incomparable.
Since education is not a means to living, but is identical with the
operation of living a life which is fruitful and inherently significant,
the only ultimate value which can be set up is just the process of living
itself. And this is not an end to which studies and activities are
subordinate means; it is the whole of which they are ingredients. And what
has been said about appreciation means that every study in one of its
aspects ought to have just such ultimate significance. It is true of
arithmetic as it is of poetry that in some place and at some time it ought
to be a good to be appreciated on its own account—just as an
enjoyable experience, in short. If it is not, then when the time and place
come for it to be used as a means or instrumentality, it will be in just
that much handicapped. Never having been realized or appreciated for
itself, one will miss something of its capacity as a resource for other
ends.</p>
<p>It equally follows that when we compare studies as to their values, that
is, treat them as means to something beyond themselves, that which
controls their proper valuation is found in the specific situation in
which they are to be used. The way to enable a student to apprehend the
instrumental value of arithmetic is not to lecture him upon the benefit it
will be to him in some remote and uncertain future, but to let him
discover that success in something he is interested in doing depends upon
ability to use number.</p>
<p>It also follows that the attempt to distribute distinct sorts of value
among different studies is a misguided one, in spite of the amount of time
recently devoted to the undertaking. Science for example may have any kind
of value, depending upon the situation into which it enters as a means. To
some the value of science may be military; it may be an instrument in
strengthening means of offense or defense; it may be technological, a tool
for engineering; or it may be commercial—an aid in the successful
conduct of business; under other conditions, its worth may be
philanthropic—the service it renders in relieving human suffering;
or again it may be quite conventional—of value in establishing one's
social status as an "educated" person. As matter of fact, science serves
all these purposes, and it would be an arbitrary task to try to fix upon
one of them as its "real" end. All that we can be sure of educationally is
that science should be taught so as to be an end in itself in the lives of
students—something worth while on account of its own unique
intrinsic contribution to the experience of life. Primarily it must have
"appreciation value." If we take something which seems to be at the
opposite pole, like poetry, the same sort of statement applies. It may be
that, at the present time, its chief value is the contribution it makes to
the enjoyment of leisure. But that may represent a degenerate condition
rather than anything necessary. Poetry has historically been allied with
religion and morals; it has served the purpose of penetrating the
mysterious depths of things. It has had an enormous patriotic value. Homer
to the Greeks was a Bible, a textbook of morals, a history, and a national
inspiration. In any case, it may be said that an education which does not
succeed in making poetry a resource in the business of life as well as in
its leisure, has something the matter with it—or else the poetry is
artificial poetry.</p>
<p>The same considerations apply to the value of a study or a topic of a
study with reference to its motivating force. Those responsible for
planning and teaching the course of study should have grounds for thinking
that the studies and topics included furnish both direct increments to the
enriching of lives of the pupils and also materials which they can put to
use in other concerns of direct interest. Since the curriculum is always
getting loaded down with purely inherited traditional matter and with
subjects which represent mainly the energy of some influential person or
group of persons in behalf of something dear to them, it requires constant
inspection, criticism, and revision to make sure it is accomplishing its
purpose. Then there is always the probability that it represents the
values of adults rather than those of children and youth, or those of
pupils a generation ago rather than those of the present day. Hence a
further need for a critical outlook and survey. But these considerations
do not mean that for a subject to have motivating value to a pupil
(whether intrinsic or instrumental) is the same thing as for him to be
aware of the value, or to be able to tell what the study is good for.</p>
<p>In the first place, as long as any topic makes an immediate appeal, it is
not necessary to ask what it is good for. This is a question which can be
asked only about instrumental values. Some goods are not good for
anything; they are just goods. Any other notion leads to an absurdity. For
we cannot stop asking the question about an instrumental good, one whose
value lies in its being good for something, unless there is at some point
something intrinsically good, good for itself. To a hungry, healthy child,
food is a good of the situation; we do not have to bring him to
consciousness of the ends subserved by food in order to supply a motive to
eat. The food in connection with his appetite is a motive. The same thing
holds of mentally eager pupils with respect to many topics. Neither they
nor the teacher could possibly foretell with any exactness the purposes
learning is to accomplish in the future; nor as long as the eagerness
continues is it advisable to try to specify particular goods which are to
come of it. The proof of a good is found in the fact that the pupil
responds; his response is use. His response to the material shows that the
subject functions in his life. It is unsound to urge that, say, Latin has
a value per se in the abstract, just as a study, as a sufficient
justification for teaching it. But it is equally absurd to argue that
unless teacher or pupil can point out some definite assignable future use
to which it is to be put, it lacks justifying value. When pupils are
genuinely concerned in learning Latin, that is of itself proof that it
possesses value. The most which one is entitled to ask in such cases is
whether in view of the shortness of time, there are not other things of
intrinsic value which in addition have greater instrumental value.</p>
<p>This brings us to the matter of instrumental values—topics studied
because of some end beyond themselves. If a child is ill and his appetite
does not lead him to eat when food is presented, or if his appetite is
perverted so that he prefers candy to meat and vegetables, conscious
reference to results is indicated. He needs to be made conscious of
consequences as a justification of the positive or negative value of
certain objects. Or the state of things may be normal enough, and yet an
individual not be moved by some matter because he does not grasp how his
attainment of some intrinsic good depends upon active concern with what is
presented. In such cases, it is obviously the part of wisdom to establish
consciousness of connection. In general what is desirable is that a topic
be presented in such a way that it either have an immediate value, and
require no justification, or else be perceived to be a means of achieving
something of intrinsic value. An instrumental value then has the intrinsic
value of being a means to an end. It may be questioned whether some of the
present pedagogical interest in the matter of values of studies is not
either excessive or else too narrow. Sometimes it appears to be a labored
effort to furnish an apologetic for topics which no longer operate to any
purpose, direct or indirect, in the lives of pupils. At other times, the
reaction against useless lumber seems to have gone to the extent of
supposing that no subject or topic should be taught unless some quite
definite future utility can be pointed out by those making the course of
study or by the pupil himself, unmindful of the fact that life is its own
excuse for being; and that definite utilities which can be pointed out are
themselves justified only because they increase the experienced content of
life itself. 3. The Segregation and Organization of Values. It is of
course possible to classify in a general way the various valuable phases
of life. In order to get a survey of aims sufficiently wide (See ante, p.
110) to give breadth and flexibility to the enterprise of education, there
is some advantage in such a classification. But it is a great mistake to
regard these values as ultimate ends to which the concrete satisfactions
of experience are subordinate. They are nothing but generalizations, more
or less adequate, of concrete goods. Health, wealth, efficiency,
sociability, utility, culture, happiness itself are only abstract terms
which sum up a multitude of particulars. To regard such things as
standards for the valuation of concrete topics and process of education is
to subordinate to an abstraction the concrete facts from which the
abstraction is derived. They are not in any true sense standards of
valuation; these are found, as we have previously seen, in the specific
realizations which form tastes and habits of preference. They are,
however, of significance as points of view elevated above the details of
life whence to survey the field and see how its constituent details are
distributed, and whether they are well proportioned. No classification can
have other than a provisional validity. The following may prove of some
help. We may say that the kind of experience to which the work of the
schools should contribute is one marked by executive competency in the
management of resources and obstacles encountered (efficiency); by
sociability, or interest in the direct companionship of others; by
aesthetic taste or capacity to appreciate artistic excellence in at least
some of its classic forms; by trained intellectual method, or interest in
some mode of scientific achievement; and by sensitiveness to the rights
and claims of others—conscientiousness. And while these
considerations are not standards of value, they are useful criteria for
survey, criticism, and better organization of existing methods and subject
matter of instruction.</p>
<p>The need of such general points of view is the greater because of a
tendency to segregate educational values due to the isolation from one
another of the various pursuits of life. The idea is prevalent that
different studies represent separate kinds of values, and that the
curriculum should, therefore, be constituted by gathering together various
studies till a sufficient variety of independent values have been cared
for. The following quotation does not use the word value, but it contains
the notion of a curriculum constructed on the idea that there are a number
of separate ends to be reached, and that various studies may be evaluated
by referring each study to its respective end. "Memory is trained by most
studies, but best by languages and history; taste is trained by the more
advanced study of languages, and still better by English literature;
imagination by all higher language teaching, but chiefly by Greek and
Latin poetry; observation by science work in the laboratory, though some
training is to be got from the earlier stages of Latin and Greek; for
expression, Greek and Latin composition comes first and English
composition next; for abstract reasoning, mathematics stands almost alone;
for concrete reasoning, science comes first, then geometry; for social
reasoning, the Greek and Roman historians and orators come first, and
general history next. Hence the narrowest education which can claim to be
at all complete includes Latin, one modern language, some history, some
English literature, and one science." There is much in the wording of this
passage which is irrelevant to our point and which must be discounted to
make it clear. The phraseology betrays the particular provincial tradition
within which the author is writing. There is the unquestioned assumption
of "faculties" to be trained, and a dominant interest in the ancient
languages; there is comparative disregard of the earth on which men happen
to live and the bodies they happen to carry around with them. But with
allowances made for these matters (even with their complete abandonment)
we find much in contemporary educational philosophy which parallels the
fundamental notion of parceling out special values to segregated studies.
Even when some one end is set up as a standard of value, like social
efficiency or culture, it will often be found to be but a verbal heading
under which a variety of disconnected factors are comprised. And although
the general tendency is to allow a greater variety of values to a given
study than does the passage quoted, yet the attempt to inventory a number
of values attaching to each study and to state the amount of each value
which the given study possesses emphasizes an implied educational
disintegration.</p>
<p>As matter of fact, such schemes of values of studies are largely but
unconscious justifications of the curriculum with which one is familiar.
One accepts, for the most part, the studies of the existing course and
then assigns values to them as a sufficient reason for their being taught.
Mathematics is said to have, for example, disciplinary value in
habituating the pupil to accuracy of statement and closeness of reasoning;
it has utilitarian value in giving command of the arts of calculation
involved in trade and the arts; culture value in its enlargement of the
imagination in dealing with the most general relations of things; even
religious value in its concept of the infinite and allied ideas. But
clearly mathematics does not accomplish such results, because it is
endowed with miraculous potencies called values; it has these values if
and when it accomplishes these results, and not otherwise. The statements
may help a teacher to a larger vision of the possible results to be
effected by instruction in mathematical topics. But unfortunately, the
tendency is to treat the statement as indicating powers inherently
residing in the subject, whether they operate or not, and thus to give it
a rigid justification. If they do not operate, the blame is put not on the
subject as taught, but on the indifference and recalcitrancy of pupils.</p>
<p>This attitude toward subjects is the obverse side of the conception of
experience or life as a patchwork of independent interests which exist
side by side and limit one another. Students of politics are familiar with
a check and balance theory of the powers of government. There are supposed
to be independent separate functions, like the legislative, executive,
judicial, administrative, and all goes well if each of these checks all
the others and thus creates an ideal balance. There is a philosophy which
might well be called the check and balance theory of experience. Life
presents a diversity of interests. Left to themselves, they tend to
encroach on one another. The ideal is to prescribe a special territory for
each till the whole ground of experience is covered, and then see to it
each remains within its own boundaries. Politics, business, recreation,
art, science, the learned professions, polite intercourse, leisure,
represent such interests. Each of these ramifies into many branches:
business into manual occupations, executive positions, bookkeeping,
railroading, banking, agriculture, trade and commerce, etc., and so with
each of the others. An ideal education would then supply the means of
meeting these separate and pigeon-holed interests. And when we look at the
schools, it is easy to get the impression that they accept this view of
the nature of adult life, and set for themselves the task of meeting its
demands. Each interest is acknowledged as a kind of fixed institution to
which something in the course of study must correspond. The course of
study must then have some civics and history politically and patriotically
viewed: some utilitarian studies; some science; some art (mainly
literature of course); some provision for recreation; some moral
education; and so on. And it will be found that a large part of current
agitation about schools is concerned with clamor and controversy about the
due meed of recognition to be given to each of these interests, and with
struggles to secure for each its due share in the course of study; or, if
this does not seem feasible in the existing school system, then to secure
a new and separate kind of schooling to meet the need. In the multitude of
educations education is forgotten.</p>
<p>The obvious outcome is congestion of the course of study, overpressure and
distraction of pupils, and a narrow specialization fatal to the very idea
of education. But these bad results usually lead to more of the same sort
of thing as a remedy. When it is perceived that after all the requirements
of a full life experience are not met, the deficiency is not laid to the
isolation and narrowness of the teaching of the existing subjects, and
this recognition made the basis of reorganization of the system. No, the
lack is something to be made up for by the introduction of still another
study, or, if necessary, another kind of school. And as a rule those who
object to the resulting overcrowding and consequent superficiality and
distraction usually also have recourse to a merely quantitative criterion:
the remedy is to cut off a great many studies as fads and frills, and
return to the good old curriculum of the three R's in elementary education
and the equally good and equally old-fashioned curriculum of the classics
and mathematics in higher education.</p>
<p>The situation has, of course, its historic explanation. Various epochs of
the past have had their own characteristic struggles and interests. Each
of these great epochs has left behind itself a kind of cultural deposit,
like a geologic stratum. These deposits have found their way into
educational institutions in the form of studies, distinct courses of
study, distinct types of schools. With the rapid change of political,
scientific, and economic interests in the last century, provision had to
be made for new values. Though the older courses resisted, they have had
at least in this country to retire their pretensions to a monopoly. They
have not, however, been reorganized in content and aim; they have only
been reduced in amount. The new studies, representing the new interests,
have not been used to transform the method and aim of all instruction;
they have been injected and added on. The result is a conglomerate, the
cement of which consists in the mechanics of the school program or time
table. Thence arises the scheme of values and standards of value which we
have mentioned.</p>
<p>This situation in education represents the divisions and separations which
obtain in social life. The variety of interests which should mark any rich
and balanced experience have been torn asunder and deposited in separate
institutions with diverse and independent purposes and methods. Business
is business, science is science, art is art, politics is politics, social
intercourse is social intercourse, morals is morals, recreation is
recreation, and so on. Each possesses a separate and independent province
with its own peculiar aims and ways of proceeding. Each contributes to the
others only externally and accidentally. All of them together make up the
whole of life by just apposition and addition. What does one expect from
business save that it should furnish money, to be used in turn for making
more money and for support of self and family, for buying books and
pictures, tickets to concerts which may afford culture, and for paying
taxes, charitable gifts and other things of social and ethical value? How
unreasonable to expect that the pursuit of business should be itself a
culture of the imagination, in breadth and refinement; that it should
directly, and not through the money which it supplies, have social service
for its animating principle and be conducted as an enterprise in behalf of
social organization! The same thing is to be said, mutatis mutandis, of
the pursuit of art or science or politics or religion. Each has become
specialized not merely in its appliances and its demands upon time, but in
its aim and animating spirit. Unconsciously, our course of studies and our
theories of the educational values of studies reflect this division of
interests. The point at issue in a theory of educational value is then the
unity or integrity of experience. How shall it be full and varied without
losing unity of spirit? How shall it be one and yet not narrow and
monotonous in its unity? Ultimately, the question of values and a standard
of values is the moral question of the organization of the interests of
life. Educationally, the question concerns that organization of schools,
materials, and methods which will operate to achieve breadth and richness
of experience. How shall we secure breadth of outlook without sacrificing
efficiency of execution? How shall we secure the diversity of interests,
without paying the price of isolation? How shall the individual be
rendered executive in his intelligence instead of at the cost of his
intelligence? How shall art, science, and politics reinforce one another
in an enriched temper of mind instead of constituting ends pursued at one
another's expense? How can the interests of life and the studies which
enforce them enrich the common experience of men instead of dividing men
from one another? With the questions of reorganization thus suggested, we
shall be concerned in the concluding chapters.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM18" id="link2H_SUMM18"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. Fundamentally, the elements involved in a discussion of value </h2>
<p>have been covered in the prior discussion of aims and interests. But since
educational values are generally discussed in connection with the claims
of the various studies of the curriculum, the consideration of aim and
interest is here resumed from the point of view of special studies. The
term "value" has two quite different meanings. On the one hand, it denotes
the attitude of prizing a thing finding it worth while, for its own sake,
or intrinsically. This is a name for a full or complete experience. To
value in this sense is to appreciate. But to value also means a
distinctively intellectual act—an operation of comparing and judging—to
valuate. This occurs when direct full experience is lacking, and the
question arises which of the various possibilities of a situation is to be
preferred in order to reach a full realization, or vital experience.</p>
<p>We must not, however, divide the studies of the curriculum into the
appreciative, those concerned with intrinsic value, and the instrumental,
concerned with those which are of value or ends beyond themselves. The
formation of proper standards in any subject depends upon a realization of
the contribution which it makes to the immediate significance of
experience, upon a direct appreciation. Literature and the fine arts are
of peculiar value because they represent appreciation at its best—a
heightened realization of meaning through selection and concentration. But
every subject at some phase of its development should possess, what is for
the individual concerned with it, an aesthetic quality.</p>
<p>Contribution to immediate intrinsic values in all their variety in
experience is the only criterion for determining the worth of instrumental
and derived values in studies. The tendency to assign separate values to
each study and to regard the curriculum in its entirety as a kind of
composite made by the aggregation of segregated values is a result of the
isolation of social groups and classes. Hence it is the business of
education in a democratic social group to struggle against this isolation
in order that the various interests may reinforce and play into one
another.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />