<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0006" id="link2H_4_0006"></SPAN></p>
<h2> DEDICATION </h2>
<p><i><br/>
To the Magnificent Lorenzo Di Piero De' Medici:<br/>
<br/>
Those who strive to obtain the good graces of a prince are<br/>
accustomed to come before him with such things as they hold most<br/>
precious, or in which they see him take most delight; whence one<br/>
often sees horses, arms, cloth of gold, precious stones, and<br/>
similar ornaments presented to princes, worthy of their greatness.<br/>
<br/>
Desiring therefore to present myself to your Magnificence with<br/>
some testimony of my devotion towards you, I have not found among<br/>
my possessions anything which I hold more dear than, or value so<br/>
much as, the knowledge of the actions of great men, acquired by<br/>
long experience in contemporary affairs, and a continual study of<br/>
antiquity; which, having reflected upon it with great and<br/>
prolonged diligence, I now send, digested into a little volume, to<br/>
your Magnificence.<br/>
<br/>
And although I may consider this work unworthy of your<br/>
countenance, nevertheless I trust much to your benignity that it<br/>
may be acceptable, seeing that it is not possible for me to make a<br/>
better gift than to offer you the opportunity of understanding in<br/>
the shortest time all that I have learnt in so many years, and<br/>
with so many troubles and dangers; which work I have not<br/>
embellished with swelling or magnificent words, nor stuffed with<br/>
rounded periods, nor with any extrinsic allurements or adornments<br/>
whatever, with which so many are accustomed to embellish their<br/>
works; for I have wished either that no honour should be given it,<br/>
or else that the truth of the matter and the weightiness of the<br/>
theme shall make it acceptable.<br/>
<br/>
Nor do I hold with those who regard it as a presumption if a man<br/>
of low and humble condition dare to discuss and settle the<br/>
concerns of princes; because, just as those who draw landscapes<br/>
place themselves below in the plain to contemplate the nature of<br/>
the mountains and of lofty places, and in order to contemplate the<br/>
plains place themselves upon high mountains, even so to understand<br/>
the nature of the people it needs to be a prince, and to<br/>
understand that of princes it needs to be of the people.<br/>
<br/>
Take then, your Magnificence, this little gift in the spirit in<br/>
which I send it; wherein, if it be diligently read and considered<br/>
by you, you will learn my extreme desire that you should attain<br/>
that greatness which fortune and your other attributes promise.<br/>
And if your Magnificence from the summit of your greatness will<br/>
sometimes turn your eyes to these lower regions, you will see how<br/>
unmeritedly I suffer a great and continued malignity of fortune.<br/>
</i></p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0007" id="link2H_4_0007"></SPAN></p>
<h2> THE PRINCE </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0001" id="link2HCH0001"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER I — HOW MANY KINDS OF PRINCIPALITIES THERE ARE, AND BY WHAT MEANS THEY ARE ACQUIRED </h2>
<p>All states, all powers, that have held and hold rule over men have been
and are either republics or principalities.</p>
<p>Principalities are either hereditary, in which the family has been long
established; or they are new.</p>
<p>The new are either entirely new, as was Milan to Francesco Sforza, or they
are, as it were, members annexed to the hereditary state of the prince who
has acquired them, as was the kingdom of Naples to that of the King of
Spain.</p>
<p>Such dominions thus acquired are either accustomed to live under a prince,
or to live in freedom; and are acquired either by the arms of the prince
himself, or of others, or else by fortune or by ability.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0002" id="link2HCH0002"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER II — CONCERNING HEREDITARY PRINCIPALITIES </h2>
<p>I will leave out all discussion on republics, inasmuch as in another place
I have written of them at length, and will address myself only to
principalities. In doing so I will keep to the order indicated above, and
discuss how such principalities are to be ruled and preserved.</p>
<p>I say at once there are fewer difficulties in holding hereditary states,
and those long accustomed to the family of their prince, than new ones;
for it is sufficient only not to transgress the customs of his ancestors,
and to deal prudently with circumstances as they arise, for a prince of
average powers to maintain himself in his state, unless he be deprived of
it by some extraordinary and excessive force; and if he should be so
deprived of it, whenever anything sinister happens to the usurper, he will
regain it.</p>
<p>We have in Italy, for example, the Duke of Ferrara, who could not have
withstood the attacks of the Venetians in '84, nor those of Pope Julius in
'10, unless he had been long established in his dominions. For the
hereditary prince has less cause and less necessity to offend; hence it
happens that he will be more loved; and unless extraordinary vices cause
him to be hated, it is reasonable to expect that his subjects will be
naturally well disposed towards him; and in the antiquity and duration of
his rule the memories and motives that make for change are lost, for one
change always leaves the toothing for another.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0003" id="link2HCH0003"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER III — CONCERNING MIXED PRINCIPALITIES </h2>
<p>But the difficulties occur in a new principality. And firstly, if it be
not entirely new, but is, as it were, a member of a state which, taken
collectively, may be called composite, the changes arise chiefly from an
inherent difficulty which there is in all new principalities; for men
change their rulers willingly, hoping to better themselves, and this hope
induces them to take up arms against him who rules: wherein they are
deceived, because they afterwards find by experience they have gone from
bad to worse. This follows also on another natural and common necessity,
which always causes a new prince to burden those who have submitted to him
with his soldiery and with infinite other hardships which he must put upon
his new acquisition.</p>
<p>In this way you have enemies in all those whom you have injured in seizing
that principality, and you are not able to keep those friends who put you
there because of your not being able to satisfy them in the way they
expected, and you cannot take strong measures against them, feeling bound
to them. For, although one may be very strong in armed forces, yet in
entering a province one has always need of the goodwill of the natives.</p>
<p>For these reasons Louis the Twelfth, King of France, quickly occupied
Milan, and as quickly lost it; and to turn him out the first time it only
needed Lodovico's own forces; because those who had opened the gates to
him, finding themselves deceived in their hopes of future benefit, would
not endure the ill-treatment of the new prince. It is very true that,
after acquiring rebellious provinces a second time, they are not so
lightly lost afterwards, because the prince, with little reluctance, takes
the opportunity of the rebellion to punish the delinquents, to clear out
the suspects, and to strengthen himself in the weakest places. Thus to
cause France to lose Milan the first time it was enough for the Duke
Lodovico(*) to raise insurrections on the borders; but to cause him to
lose it a second time it was necessary to bring the whole world against
him, and that his armies should be defeated and driven out of Italy; which
followed from the causes above mentioned.</p>
<p>(*) Duke Lodovico was Lodovico Moro, a son of Francesco<br/>
Sforza, who married Beatrice d'Este. He ruled over Milan<br/>
from 1494 to 1500, and died in 1510.<br/></p>
<p>Nevertheless Milan was taken from France both the first and the second
time. The general reasons for the first have been discussed; it remains to
name those for the second, and to see what resources he had, and what any
one in his situation would have had for maintaining himself more securely
in his acquisition than did the King of France.</p>
<p>Now I say that those dominions which, when acquired, are added to an
ancient state by him who acquires them, are either of the same country and
language, or they are not. When they are, it is easier to hold them,
especially when they have not been accustomed to self-government; and to
hold them securely it is enough to have destroyed the family of the prince
who was ruling them; because the two peoples, preserving in other things
the old conditions, and not being unlike in customs, will live quietly
together, as one has seen in Brittany, Burgundy, Gascony, and Normandy,
which have been bound to France for so long a time: and, although there
may be some difference in language, nevertheless the customs are alike,
and the people will easily be able to get on amongst themselves. He who
has annexed them, if he wishes to hold them, has only to bear in mind two
considerations: the one, that the family of their former lord is
extinguished; the other, that neither their laws nor their taxes are
altered, so that in a very short time they will become entirely one body
with the old principality.</p>
<p>But when states are acquired in a country differing in language, customs,
or laws, there are difficulties, and good fortune and great energy are
needed to hold them, and one of the greatest and most real helps would be
that he who has acquired them should go and reside there. This would make
his position more secure and durable, as it has made that of the Turk in
Greece, who, notwithstanding all the other measures taken by him for
holding that state, if he had not settled there, would not have been able
to keep it. Because, if one is on the spot, disorders are seen as they
spring up, and one can quickly remedy them; but if one is not at hand,
they are heard of only when they are great, and then one can no longer
remedy them. Besides this, the country is not pillaged by your officials;
the subjects are satisfied by prompt recourse to the prince; thus, wishing
to be good, they have more cause to love him, and wishing to be otherwise,
to fear him. He who would attack that state from the outside must have the
utmost caution; as long as the prince resides there it can only be wrested
from him with the greatest difficulty.</p>
<p>The other and better course is to send colonies to one or two places,
which may be as keys to that state, for it is necessary either to do this
or else to keep there a great number of cavalry and infantry. A prince
does not spend much on colonies, for with little or no expense he can send
them out and keep them there, and he offends a minority only of the
citizens from whom he takes lands and houses to give them to the new
inhabitants; and those whom he offends, remaining poor and scattered, are
never able to injure him; whilst the rest being uninjured are easily kept
quiet, and at the same time are anxious not to err for fear it should
happen to them as it has to those who have been despoiled. In conclusion,
I say that these colonies are not costly, they are more faithful, they
injure less, and the injured, as has been said, being poor and scattered,
cannot hurt. Upon this, one has to remark that men ought either to be well
treated or crushed, because they can avenge themselves of lighter
injuries, of more serious ones they cannot; therefore the injury that is
to be done to a man ought to be of such a kind that one does not stand in
fear of revenge.</p>
<p>But in maintaining armed men there in place of colonies one spends much
more, having to consume on the garrison all the income from the state, so
that the acquisition turns into a loss, and many more are exasperated,
because the whole state is injured; through the shifting of the garrison
up and down all become acquainted with hardship, and all become hostile,
and they are enemies who, whilst beaten on their own ground, are yet able
to do hurt. For every reason, therefore, such guards are as useless as a
colony is useful.</p>
<p>Again, the prince who holds a country differing in the above respects
ought to make himself the head and defender of his less powerful
neighbours, and to weaken the more powerful amongst them, taking care that
no foreigner as powerful as himself shall, by any accident, get a footing
there; for it will always happen that such a one will be introduced by
those who are discontented, either through excess of ambition or through
fear, as one has seen already. The Romans were brought into Greece by the
Aetolians; and in every other country where they obtained a footing they
were brought in by the inhabitants. And the usual course of affairs is
that, as soon as a powerful foreigner enters a country, all the subject
states are drawn to him, moved by the hatred which they feel against the
ruling power. So that in respect to those subject states he has not to
take any trouble to gain them over to himself, for the whole of them
quickly rally to the state which he has acquired there. He has only to
take care that they do not get hold of too much power and too much
authority, and then with his own forces, and with their goodwill, he can
easily keep down the more powerful of them, so as to remain entirely
master in the country. And he who does not properly manage this business
will soon lose what he has acquired, and whilst he does hold it he will
have endless difficulties and troubles.</p>
<p>The Romans, in the countries which they annexed, observed closely these
measures; they sent colonies and maintained friendly relations with(*) the
minor powers, without increasing their strength; they kept down the
greater, and did not allow any strong foreign powers to gain authority.
Greece appears to me sufficient for an example. The Achaeans and Aetolians
were kept friendly by them, the kingdom of Macedonia was humbled,
Antiochus was driven out; yet the merits of the Achaeans and Aetolians
never secured for them permission to increase their power, nor did the
persuasions of Philip ever induce the Romans to be his friends without
first humbling him, nor did the influence of Antiochus make them agree
that he should retain any lordship over the country. Because the Romans
did in these instances what all prudent princes ought to do, who have to
regard not only present troubles, but also future ones, for which they
must prepare with every energy, because, when foreseen, it is easy to
remedy them; but if you wait until they approach, the medicine is no
longer in time because the malady has become incurable; for it happens in
this, as the physicians say it happens in hectic fever, that in the
beginning of the malady it is easy to cure but difficult to detect, but in
the course of time, not having been either detected or treated in the
beginning, it becomes easy to detect but difficult to cure. This it
happens in affairs of state, for when the evils that arise have been
foreseen (which it is only given to a wise man to see), they can be
quickly redressed, but when, through not having been foreseen, they have
been permitted to grow in a way that every one can see them, there is no
longer a remedy. Therefore, the Romans, foreseeing troubles, dealt with
them at once, and, even to avoid a war, would not let them come to a head,
for they knew that war is not to be avoided, but is only to be put off to
the advantage of others; moreover they wished to fight with Philip and
Antiochus in Greece so as not to have to do it in Italy; they could have
avoided both, but this they did not wish; nor did that ever please them
which is for ever in the mouths of the wise ones of our time:—Let us
enjoy the benefits of the time—but rather the benefits of their own
valour and prudence, for time drives everything before it, and is able to
bring with it good as well as evil, and evil as well as good.</p>
<p>(*) See remark in the introduction on the word<br/>
"intrattenere."<br/></p>
<p>But let us turn to France and inquire whether she has done any of the
things mentioned. I will speak of Louis(*) (and not of Charles)(+) as the
one whose conduct is the better to be observed, he having held possession
of Italy for the longest period; and you will see that he has done the
opposite to those things which ought to be done to retain a state composed
of divers elements.</p>
<p>(*) Louis XII, King of France, "The Father of the People,"<br/>
born 1462, died 1515.<br/>
<br/>
(+) Charles VIII, King of France, born 1470, died 1498.<br/></p>
<p>King Louis was brought into Italy by the ambition of the Venetians, who
desired to obtain half the state of Lombardy by his intervention. I will
not blame the course taken by the king, because, wishing to get a foothold
in Italy, and having no friends there—seeing rather that every door
was shut to him owing to the conduct of Charles—he was forced to
accept those friendships which he could get, and he would have succeeded
very quickly in his design if in other matters he had not made some
mistakes. The king, however, having acquired Lombardy, regained at once
the authority which Charles had lost: Genoa yielded; the Florentines
became his friends; the Marquess of Mantua, the Duke of Ferrara, the
Bentivogli, my lady of Forli, the Lords of Faenza, of Pesaro, of Rimini,
of Camerino, of Piombino, the Lucchese, the Pisans, the Sienese—everybody
made advances to him to become his friend. Then could the Venetians
realize the rashness of the course taken by them, which, in order that
they might secure two towns in Lombardy, had made the king master of
two-thirds of Italy.</p>
<p>Let any one now consider with what little difficulty the king could have
maintained his position in Italy had he observed the rules above laid
down, and kept all his friends secure and protected; for although they
were numerous they were both weak and timid, some afraid of the Church,
some of the Venetians, and thus they would always have been forced to
stand in with him, and by their means he could easily have made himself
secure against those who remained powerful. But he was no sooner in Milan
than he did the contrary by assisting Pope Alexander to occupy the
Romagna. It never occurred to him that by this action he was weakening
himself, depriving himself of friends and of those who had thrown
themselves into his lap, whilst he aggrandized the Church by adding much
temporal power to the spiritual, thus giving it greater authority. And
having committed this prime error, he was obliged to follow it up, so much
so that, to put an end to the ambition of Alexander, and to prevent his
becoming the master of Tuscany, he was himself forced to come into Italy.</p>
<p>And as if it were not enough to have aggrandized the Church, and deprived
himself of friends, he, wishing to have the kingdom of Naples, divides it
with the King of Spain, and where he was the prime arbiter in Italy he
takes an associate, so that the ambitious of that country and the
malcontents of his own should have somewhere to shelter; and whereas he
could have left in the kingdom his own pensioner as king, he drove him
out, to put one there who was able to drive him, Louis, out in turn.</p>
<p>The wish to acquire is in truth very natural and common, and men always do
so when they can, and for this they will be praised not blamed; but when
they cannot do so, yet wish to do so by any means, then there is folly and
blame. Therefore, if France could have attacked Naples with her own forces
she ought to have done so; if she could not, then she ought not to have
divided it. And if the partition which she made with the Venetians in
Lombardy was justified by the excuse that by it she got a foothold in
Italy, this other partition merited blame, for it had not the excuse of
that necessity.</p>
<p>Therefore Louis made these five errors: he destroyed the minor powers, he
increased the strength of one of the greater powers in Italy, he brought
in a foreign power, he did not settle in the country, he did not send
colonies. Which errors, had he lived, were not enough to injure him had he
not made a sixth by taking away their dominions from the Venetians;
because, had he not aggrandized the Church, nor brought Spain into Italy,
it would have been very reasonable and necessary to humble them; but
having first taken these steps, he ought never to have consented to their
ruin, for they, being powerful, would always have kept off others from
designs on Lombardy, to which the Venetians would never have consented
except to become masters themselves there; also because the others would
not wish to take Lombardy from France in order to give it to the
Venetians, and to run counter to both they would not have had the courage.</p>
<p>And if any one should say: "King Louis yielded the Romagna to Alexander
and the kingdom to Spain to avoid war," I answer for the reasons given
above that a blunder ought never to be perpetrated to avoid war, because
it is not to be avoided, but is only deferred to your disadvantage. And if
another should allege the pledge which the king had given to the Pope that
he would assist him in the enterprise, in exchange for the dissolution of
his marriage(*) and for the cap to Rouen,(+) to that I reply what I shall
write later on concerning the faith of princes, and how it ought to be
kept.</p>
<p>(*) Louis XII divorced his wife, Jeanne, daughter of Louis<br/>
XI, and married in 1499 Anne of Brittany, widow of Charles<br/>
VIII, in order to retain the Duchy of Brittany for the<br/>
crown.<br/>
<br/>
(+) The Archbishop of Rouen. He was Georges d'Amboise,<br/>
created a cardinal by Alexander VI. Born 1460, died 1510.<br/></p>
<p>Thus King Louis lost Lombardy by not having followed any of the conditions
observed by those who have taken possession of countries and wished to
retain them. Nor is there any miracle in this, but much that is reasonable
and quite natural. And on these matters I spoke at Nantes with Rouen, when
Valentino, as Cesare Borgia, the son of Pope Alexander, was usually
called, occupied the Romagna, and on Cardinal Rouen observing to me that
the Italians did not understand war, I replied to him that the French did
not understand statecraft, meaning that otherwise they would not have
allowed the Church to reach such greatness. And in fact is has been seen
that the greatness of the Church and of Spain in Italy has been caused by
France, and her ruin may be attributed to them. From this a general rule
is drawn which never or rarely fails: that he who is the cause of another
becoming powerful is ruined; because that predominancy has been brought
about either by astuteness or else by force, and both are distrusted by
him who has been raised to power.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0004" id="link2HCH0004"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER IV — WHY THE KINGDOM OF DARIUS, CONQUERED BY ALEXANDER, DID NOT REBEL AGAINST THE SUCCESSORS OF ALEXANDER AT HIS DEATH </h2>
<p>Considering the difficulties which men have had to hold to a newly
acquired state, some might wonder how, seeing that Alexander the Great
became the master of Asia in a few years, and died whilst it was scarcely
settled (whence it might appear reasonable that the whole empire would
have rebelled), nevertheless his successors maintained themselves, and had
to meet no other difficulty than that which arose among themselves from
their own ambitions.</p>
<p>I answer that the principalities of which one has record are found to be
governed in two different ways; either by a prince, with a body of
servants, who assist him to govern the kingdom as ministers by his favour
and permission; or by a prince and barons, who hold that dignity by
antiquity of blood and not by the grace of the prince. Such barons have
states and their own subjects, who recognize them as lords and hold them
in natural affection. Those states that are governed by a prince and his
servants hold their prince in more consideration, because in all the
country there is no one who is recognized as superior to him, and if they
yield obedience to another they do it as to a minister and official, and
they do not bear him any particular affection.</p>
<p>The examples of these two governments in our time are the Turk and the
King of France. The entire monarchy of the Turk is governed by one lord,
the others are his servants; and, dividing his kingdom into sanjaks, he
sends there different administrators, and shifts and changes them as he
chooses. But the King of France is placed in the midst of an ancient body
of lords, acknowledged by their own subjects, and beloved by them; they
have their own prerogatives, nor can the king take these away except at
his peril. Therefore, he who considers both of these states will recognize
great difficulties in seizing the state of the Turk, but, once it is
conquered, great ease in holding it. The causes of the difficulties in
seizing the kingdom of the Turk are that the usurper cannot be called in
by the princes of the kingdom, nor can he hope to be assisted in his
designs by the revolt of those whom the lord has around him. This arises
from the reasons given above; for his ministers, being all slaves and
bondmen, can only be corrupted with great difficulty, and one can expect
little advantage from them when they have been corrupted, as they cannot
carry the people with them, for the reasons assigned. Hence, he who
attacks the Turk must bear in mind that he will find him united, and he
will have to rely more on his own strength than on the revolt of others;
but, if once the Turk has been conquered, and routed in the field in such
a way that he cannot replace his armies, there is nothing to fear but the
family of this prince, and, this being exterminated, there remains no one
to fear, the others having no credit with the people; and as the conqueror
did not rely on them before his victory, so he ought not to fear them
after it.</p>
<p>The contrary happens in kingdoms governed like that of France, because one
can easily enter there by gaining over some baron of the kingdom, for one
always finds malcontents and such as desire a change. Such men, for the
reasons given, can open the way into the state and render the victory
easy; but if you wish to hold it afterwards, you meet with infinite
difficulties, both from those who have assisted you and from those you
have crushed. Nor is it enough for you to have exterminated the family of
the prince, because the lords that remain make themselves the heads of
fresh movements against you, and as you are unable either to satisfy or
exterminate them, that state is lost whenever time brings the opportunity.</p>
<p>Now if you will consider what was the nature of the government of Darius,
you will find it similar to the kingdom of the Turk, and therefore it was
only necessary for Alexander, first to overthrow him in the field, and
then to take the country from him. After which victory, Darius being
killed, the state remained secure to Alexander, for the above reasons. And
if his successors had been united they would have enjoyed it securely and
at their ease, for there were no tumults raised in the kingdom except
those they provoked themselves.</p>
<p>But it is impossible to hold with such tranquillity states constituted
like that of France. Hence arose those frequent rebellions against the
Romans in Spain, France, and Greece, owing to the many principalities
there were in these states, of which, as long as the memory of them
endured, the Romans always held an insecure possession; but with the power
and long continuance of the empire the memory of them passed away, and the
Romans then became secure possessors. And when fighting afterwards amongst
themselves, each one was able to attach to himself his own parts of the
country, according to the authority he had assumed there; and the family
of the former lord being exterminated, none other than the Romans were
acknowledged.</p>
<p>When these things are remembered no one will marvel at the ease with which
Alexander held the Empire of Asia, or at the difficulties which others
have had to keep an acquisition, such as Pyrrhus and many more; this is
not occasioned by the little or abundance of ability in the conqueror, but
by the want of uniformity in the subject state.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0005" id="link2HCH0005"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER V — CONCERNING THE WAY TO GOVERN CITIES OR PRINCIPALITIES WHICH LIVED UNDER THEIR OWN LAWS BEFORE THEY WERE ANNEXED </h2>
<p>Whenever those states which have been acquired as stated have been
accustomed to live under their own laws and in freedom, there are three
courses for those who wish to hold them: the first is to ruin them, the
next is to reside there in person, the third is to permit them to live
under their own laws, drawing a tribute, and establishing within it an
oligarchy which will keep it friendly to you. Because such a government,
being created by the prince, knows that it cannot stand without his
friendship and interest, and does it utmost to support him; and therefore
he who would keep a city accustomed to freedom will hold it more easily by
the means of its own citizens than in any other way.</p>
<p>There are, for example, the Spartans and the Romans. The Spartans held
Athens and Thebes, establishing there an oligarchy, nevertheless they lost
them. The Romans, in order to hold Capua, Carthage, and Numantia,
dismantled them, and did not lose them. They wished to hold Greece as the
Spartans held it, making it free and permitting its laws, and did not
succeed. So to hold it they were compelled to dismantle many cities in the
country, for in truth there is no safe way to retain them otherwise than
by ruining them. And he who becomes master of a city accustomed to freedom
and does not destroy it, may expect to be destroyed by it, for in
rebellion it has always the watchword of liberty and its ancient
privileges as a rallying point, which neither time nor benefits will ever
cause it to forget. And whatever you may do or provide against, they never
forget that name or their privileges unless they are disunited or
dispersed, but at every chance they immediately rally to them, as Pisa
after the hundred years she had been held in bondage by the Florentines.</p>
<p>But when cities or countries are accustomed to live under a prince, and
his family is exterminated, they, being on the one hand accustomed to obey
and on the other hand not having the old prince, cannot agree in making
one from amongst themselves, and they do not know how to govern
themselves. For this reason they are very slow to take up arms, and a
prince can gain them to himself and secure them much more easily. But in
republics there is more vitality, greater hatred, and more desire for
vengeance, which will never permit them to allow the memory of their
former liberty to rest; so that the safest way is to destroy them or to
reside there.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />