<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0020" id="link2HCH0020"></SPAN></p>
<h2> Chapter VIII: The Federal Constitution—Part III </h2>
<h3> Re-election Of The President </h3>
<p>When the head of the executive power is re-eligible, it is the State which
is the source of intrigue and corruption—The desire of being
re-elected the chief aim of a President of the United States—Disadvantage
of the system peculiar to America—The natural evil of democracy is
that it subordinates all authority to the slightest desires of the
majority—The re-election of the President encourages this evil.</p>
<p>It may be asked whether the legislators of the United States did right or
wrong in allowing the re-election of the President. It seems at first
sight contrary to all reason to prevent the head of the executive power
from being elected a second time. The influence which the talents and the
character of a single individual may exercise upon the fate of a whole
people, in critical circumstances or arduous times, is well known: a law
preventing the re-election of the chief magistrate would deprive the
citizens of the surest pledge of the prosperity and the security of the
commonwealth; and, by a singular inconsistency, a man would be excluded
from the government at the very time when he had shown his ability in
conducting its affairs.</p>
<p>But if these arguments are strong, perhaps still more powerful reasons may
be advanced against them. Intrigue and corruption are the natural defects
of elective government; but when the head of the State can be re-elected
these evils rise to a great height, and compromise the very existence of
the country. When a simple candidate seeks to rise by intrigue, his
manoeuvres must necessarily be limited to a narrow sphere; but when the
chief magistrate enters the lists, he borrows the strength of the
government for his own purposes. In the former case the feeble resources
of an individual are in action; in the latter, the State itself, with all
its immense influence, is busied in the work of corruption and cabal. The
private citizen, who employs the most immoral practices to acquire power,
can only act in a manner indirectly prejudicial to the public prosperity.
But if the representative of the executive descends into the combat, the
cares of government dwindle into second-rate importance, and the success
of his election is his first concern. All laws and all the negotiations he
undertakes are to him nothing more than electioneering schemes; places
become the reward of services rendered, not to the nation, but to its
chief; and the influence of the government, if not injurious to the
country, is at least no longer beneficial to the community for which it
was created.</p>
<p>It is impossible to consider the ordinary course of affairs in the United
States without perceiving that the desire of being re-elected is the chief
aim of the President; that his whole administration, and even his most
indifferent measures, tend to this object; and that, as the crisis
approaches, his personal interest takes the place of his interest in the
public good. The principle of re-eligibility renders the corrupt influence
of elective government still more extensive and pernicious.</p>
<p>In America it exercises a peculiarly fatal influence on the sources of
national existence. Every government seems to be afflicted by some evil
which is inherent in its nature, and the genius of the legislator is shown
in eluding its attacks. A State may survive the influence of a host of bad
laws, and the mischief they cause is frequently exaggerated; but a law
which encourages the growth of the canker within must prove fatal in the
end, although its bad consequences may not be immediately perceived.</p>
<p>The principle of destruction in absolute monarchies lies in the excessive
and unreasonable extension of the prerogative of the crown; and a measure
tending to remove the constitutional provisions which counterbalance this
influence would be radically bad, even if its immediate consequences were
unattended with evil. By a parity of reasoning, in countries governed by a
democracy, where the people is perpetually drawing all authority to
itself, the laws which increase or accelerate its action are the direct
assailants of the very principle of the government.</p>
<p>The greatest proof of the ability of the American legislators is, that
they clearly discerned this truth, and that they had the courage to act up
to it. They conceived that a certain authority above the body of the
people was necessary, which should enjoy a degree of independence,
without, however, being entirely beyond the popular control; an authority
which would be forced to comply with the permanent determinations of the
majority, but which would be able to resist its caprices, and to refuse
its most dangerous demands. To this end they centred the whole executive
power of the nation in a single arm; they granted extensive prerogatives
to the President, and they armed him with the veto to resist the
encroachments of the legislature.</p>
<p>But by introducing the principle of re-election they partly destroyed
their work; and they rendered the President but little inclined to exert
the great power they had vested in his hands. If ineligible a second time,
the President would be far from independent of the people, for his
responsibility would not be lessened; but the favor of the people would
not be so necessary to him as to induce him to court it by humoring its
desires. If re-eligible (and this is more especially true at the present
day, when political morality is relaxed, and when great men are rare), the
President of the United States becomes an easy tool in the hands of the
majority. He adopts its likings and its animosities, he hastens to
anticipate its wishes, he forestalls its complaints, he yields to its
idlest cravings, and instead of guiding it, as the legislature intended
that he should do, he is ever ready to follow its bidding. Thus, in order
not to deprive the State of the talents of an individual, those talents
have been rendered almost useless; and to reserve an expedient for
extraordinary perils, the country has been exposed to daily dangers.</p>
<p>Federal Courts *b</p>
<p class="foot">
b <br/> [ See chap. VI, entitled "Judicial Power in the United States."
This chapter explains the general principles of the American theory of
judicial institutions. See also the Federal Constitution, Art. 3. See "The
Federalists," Nos. 78-83, inclusive; and a work entitled "Constitutional
Law," being a view of the practice and jurisdiction of the courts of the
United States, by Thomas Sergeant. See Story, pp. 134, 162, 489, 511, 581,
668; and the organic law of September 24, 1789, in the "Collection of the
Laws of the United States," by Story, vol. i. p. 53.]</p>
<p>Political importance of the judiciary in the United States—Difficulty
of treating this subject—Utility of judicial power in confederations—What
tribunals could be introduced into the Union—Necessity of
establishing federal courts of justice—Organization of the national
judiciary—The Supreme Court—In what it differs from all known
tribunals.</p>
<p>I have inquired into the legislative and executive power of the Union, and
the judicial power now remains to be examined; but in this place I cannot
conceal my fears from the reader. Their judicial institutions exercise a
great influence on the condition of the Anglo-Americans, and they occupy a
prominent place amongst what are probably called political institutions:
in this respect they are peculiarly deserving of our attention. But I am
at a loss to explain the political action of the American tribunals
without entering into some technical details of their constitution and
their forms of proceeding; and I know not how to descend to these minutiae
without wearying the curiosity of the reader by the natural aridity of the
subject, or without risking to fall into obscurity through a desire to be
succinct. I can scarcely hope to escape these various evils; for if I
appear too lengthy to a man of the world, a lawyer may on the other hand
complain of my brevity. But these are the natural disadvantages of my
subject, and more especially of the point which I am about to discuss.</p>
<p>The great difficulty was, not to devise the Constitution to the Federal
Government, but to find out a method of enforcing its laws. Governments
have in general but two means of overcoming the opposition of the people
they govern, viz., the physical force which is at their own disposal, and
the moral force which they derive from the decisions of the courts of
justice.</p>
<p>A government which should have no other means of exacting obedience than
open war must be very near its ruin, for one of two alternatives would
then probably occur: if its authority was small and its character
temperate, it would not resort to violence till the last extremity, and it
would connive at a number of partial acts of insubordination, in which
case the State would gradually fall into anarchy; if it was enterprising
and powerful, it would perpetually have recourse to its physical strength,
and would speedily degenerate into a military despotism. So that its
activity would not be less prejudicial to the community than its inaction.</p>
<p>The great end of justice is to substitute the notion of right for that of
violence, and to place a legal barrier between the power of the government
and the use of physical force. The authority which is awarded to the
intervention of a court of justice by the general opinion of mankind is so
surprisingly great that it clings to the mere formalities of justice, and
gives a bodily influence to the shadow of the law. The moral force which
courts of justice possess renders the introduction of physical force
exceedingly rare, and is very frequently substituted for it; but if the
latter proves to be indispensable, its power is doubled by the association
of the idea of law.</p>
<p>A federal government stands in greater need of the support of judicial
institutions than any other, because it is naturally weak and exposed to
formidable opposition. *c If it were always obliged to resort to violence
in the first instance, it could not fulfil its task. The Union, therefore,
required a national judiciary to enforce the obedience of the citizens to
the laws, and to repeal the attacks which might be directed against them.
The question then remained as to what tribunals were to exercise these
privileges; were they to be entrusted to the courts of justice which were
already organized in every State? or was it necessary to create federal
courts? It may easily be proved that the Union could not adapt the
judicial power of the States to its wants. The separation of the judiciary
from the administrative power of the State no doubt affects the security
of every citizen and the liberty of all. But it is no less important to
the existence of the nation that these several powers should have the same
origin, should follow the same principles, and act in the same sphere; in
a word, that they should be correlative and homogeneous. No one, I
presume, ever suggested the advantage of trying offences committed in
France by a foreign court of justice, in order to secure the impartiality
of the judges. The Americans form one people in relation to their Federal
Government; but in the bosom of this people divers political bodies have
been allowed to subsist which are dependent on the national Government in
a few points, and independent in all the rest; which have all a distinct
origin, maxims peculiar to themselves, and special means of carrying on
their affairs. To entrust the execution of the laws of the Union to
tribunals instituted by these political bodies would be to allow foreign
judges to preside over the nation. Nay, more; not only is each State
foreign to the Union at large, but it is in perpetual opposition to the
common interests, since whatever authority the Union loses turns to the
advantage of the States. Thus to enforce the laws of the Union by means of
the tribunals of the States would be to allow not only foreign but partial
judges to preside over the nation.</p>
<p class="foot">
c <br/> [ Federal laws are those which most require courts of justice, and
those at the same time which have most rarely established them. The reason
is that confederations have usually been formed by independent States,
which entertained no real intention of obeying the central Government, and
which very readily ceded the right of command to the federal executive,
and very prudently reserved the right of non-compliance to themselves.]</p>
<p>But the number, still more than the mere character, of the tribunals of
the States rendered them unfit for the service of the nation. When the
Federal Constitution was formed there were already thirteen courts of
justice in the United States which decided causes without appeal. That
number is now increased to twenty-four. To suppose that a State can
subsist when its fundamental laws may be subjected to four-and-twenty
different interpretations at the same time is to advance a proposition
alike contrary to reason and to experience.</p>
<p>The American legislators therefore agreed to create a federal judiciary
power to apply the laws of the Union, and to determine certain questions
affecting general interests, which were carefully determined beforehand.
The entire judicial power of the Union was centred in one tribunal, which
was denominated the Supreme Court of the United States. But, to facilitate
the expedition of business, inferior courts were appended to it, which
were empowered to decide causes of small importance without appeal, and
with appeal causes of more magnitude. The members of the Supreme Court are
named neither by the people nor the legislature, but by the President of
the United States, acting with the advice of the Senate. In order to
render them independent of the other authorities, their office was made
inalienable; and it was determined that their salary, when once fixed,
should not be altered by the legislature. *d It was easy to proclaim the
principle of a Federal judiciary, but difficulties multiplied when the
extent of its jurisdiction was to be determined.</p>
<p class="foot">
d <br/> [ The Union was divided into districts, in each of which a
resident Federal judge was appointed, and the court in which he presided
was termed a "District Court." Each of the judges of the Supreme Court
annually visits a certain portion of the Republic, in order to try the
most important causes upon the spot; the court presided over by this
magistrate is styled a "Circuit Court." Lastly, all the most serious cases
of litigation are brought before the Supreme Court, which holds a solemn
session once a year, at which all the judges of the Circuit Courts must
attend. The jury was introduced into the Federal Courts in the same
manner, and in the same cases, as into the courts of the States.</p>
<p>It will be observed that no analogy exists between the Supreme Court of
the United States and the French Cour de Cassation, since the latter only
hears appeals on questions of law. The Supreme Court decides upon the
evidence of the fact as well as upon the law of the case, whereas the Cour
de Cassation does not pronounce a decision of its own, but refers the
cause to the arbitration of another tribunal. See the law of September 24,
1789, "Laws of the United States," by Story, vol. i. p. 53.]</p>
<p>Means Of Determining The Jurisdiction Of The Federal Courts Difficulty of
determining the jurisdiction of separate courts of justice in
confederations—The courts of the Union obtained the right of fixing
their own jurisdiction—In what respect this rule attacks the portion
of sovereignty reserved to the several States—The sovereignty of
these States restricted by the laws, and the interpretation of the laws—Consequently,
the danger of the several States is more apparent than real.</p>
<p>As the Constitution of the United States recognized two distinct powers in
presence of each other, represented in a judicial point of view by two
distinct classes of courts of justice, the utmost care which could be
taken in defining their separate jurisdictions would have been
insufficient to prevent frequent collisions between those tribunals. The
question then arose to whom the right of deciding the competency of each
court was to be referred.</p>
<p>In nations which constitute a single body politic, when a question is
debated between two courts relating to their mutual jurisdiction, a third
tribunal is generally within reach to decide the difference; and this is
effected without difficulty, because in these nations the questions of
judicial competency have no connection with the privileges of the national
supremacy. But it was impossible to create an arbiter between a superior
court of the Union and the superior court of a separate State which would
not belong to one of these two classes. It was, therefore, necessary to
allow one of these courts to judge its own cause, and to take or to retain
cognizance of the point which was contested. To grant this privilege to
the different courts of the States would have been to destroy the
sovereignty of the Union de facto after having established it de jure; for
the interpretation of the Constitution would soon have restored that
portion of independence to the States of which the terms of that act
deprived them. The object of the creation of a Federal tribunal was to
prevent the courts of the States from deciding questions affecting the
national interests in their own department, and so to form a uniform body
of jurisprudene for the interpretation of the laws of the Union. This end
would not have been accomplished if the courts of the several States had
been competent to decide upon cases in their separate capacities from
which they were obliged to abstain as Federal tribunals. The Supreme Court
of the United States was therefore invested with the right of determining
all questions of jurisdiction. *e</p>
<p class="foot">
e <br/> [ In order to diminish the number of these suits, it was decided
that in a great many Federal causes the courts of the States should be
empowered to decide conjointly with those of the Union, the losing party
having then a right of appeal to the Supreme Court of the United States.
The Supreme Court of Virginia contested the right of the Supreme Court of
the United States to judge an appeal from its decisions, but
unsuccessfully. See "Kent's Commentaries," vol. i. p. 300, pp. 370 et
seq.; Story's "Commentaries," p. 646; and "The Organic Law of the United
States," vol. i. p. 35.]</p>
<p>This was a severe blow upon the independence of the States, which was thus
restricted not only by the laws, but by the interpretation of them; by one
limit which was known, and by another which was dubious; by a rule which
was certain, and a rule which was arbitrary. It is true the Constitution
had laid down the precise limits of the Federal supremacy, but whenever
this supremacy is contested by one of the States, a Federal tribunal
decides the question. Nevertheless, the dangers with which the
independence of the States was threatened by this mode of proceeding are
less serious than they appeared to be. We shall see hereafter that in
America the real strength of the country is vested in the provincial far
more than in the Federal Government. The Federal judges are conscious of
the relative weakness of the power in whose name they act, and they are
more inclined to abandon a right of jurisdiction in cases where it is
justly their own than to assert a privilege to which they have no legal
claim.</p>
<p>Different Cases Of Jurisdiction</p>
<p>The matter and the party are the first conditions of the Federal
jurisdiction—Suits in which ambassadors are engaged—Suits of
the Union—Of a separate State—By whom tried—Causes
resulting from the laws of the Union—Why judged by the Federal
tribunals—Causes relating to the performance of contracts tried by
the Federal courts—Consequence of this arrangement.</p>
<p>After having appointed the means of fixing the competency of the Federal
courts, the legislators of the Union defined the cases which should come
within their jurisdiction. It was established, on the one hand, that
certain parties must always be brought before the Federal courts, without
any regard to the special nature of the cause; and, on the other, that
certain causes must always be brought before the same courts, without any
regard to the quality of the parties in the suit. These distinctions were
therefore admitted to be the basis of the Federal jurisdiction.</p>
<p>Ambassadors are the representatives of nations in a state of amity with
the Union, and whatever concerns these personages concerns in some degree
the whole Union. When an ambassador is a party in a suit, that suit
affects the welfare of the nation, and a Federal tribunal is naturally
called upon to decide it.</p>
<p>The Union itself may be invoked in legal proceedings, and in this case it
would be alike contrary to the customs of all nations and to common sense
to appeal to a tribunal representing any other sovereignty than its own;
the Federal courts, therefore, take cognizance of these affairs.</p>
<p>When two parties belonging to two different States are engaged in a suit,
the case cannot with propriety be brought before a court of either State.
The surest expedient is to select a tribunal like that of the Union, which
can excite the suspicions of neither party, and which offers the most
natural as well as the most certain remedy.</p>
<p>When the two parties are not private individuals, but States, an important
political consideration is added to the same motive of equity. The quality
of the parties in this case gives a national importance to all their
disputes; and the most trifling litigation of the States may be said to
involve the peace of the whole Union. *f</p>
<p class="foot">
f <br/> [ The Constitution also says that the Federal courts shall decide
"controversies between a State and the citizens of another State." And
here a most important question of a constitutional nature arose, which
was, whether the jurisdiction given by the Constitution in cases in which
a State is a party extended to suits brought against a State as well as by
it, or was exclusively confined to the latter. The question was most
elaborately considered in the case of Chisholm v. Georgia, and was decided
by the majority of the Supreme Court in the affirmative. The decision
created general alarm among the States, and an amendment was proposed and
ratified by which the power was entirely taken away, so far as it regards
suits brought against a State. See Story's "Commentaries," p. 624, or in
the large edition Section 1677.]</p>
<p>The nature of the cause frequently prescribes the rule of competency. Thus
all the questions which concern maritime commerce evidently fall under the
cognizance of the Federal tribunals. *g Almost all these questions are
connected with the interpretation of the law of nations, and in this
respect they essentially interest the Union in relation to foreign powers.
Moreover, as the sea is not included within the limits of any peculiar
jurisdiction, the national courts can only hear causes which originate in
maritime affairs.</p>
<p class="foot">
g <br/> [ As for instance, all cases of piracy.]</p>
<p>The Constitution comprises under one head almost all the cases which by
their very nature come within the limits of the Federal courts. The rule
which it lays down is simple, but pregnant with an entire system of ideas,
and with a vast multitude of facts. It declares that the judicial power of
the Supreme Court shall extend to all cases in law and equity arising
under the laws of the United States.</p>
<p>Two examples will put the intention of the legislator in the clearest
light:</p>
<p>The Constitution prohibits the States from making laws on the value and
circulation of money: If, notwithstanding this prohibition, a State passes
a law of this kind, with which the interested parties refuse to comply
because it is contrary to the Constitution, the case must come before a
Federal court, because it arises under the laws of the United States.
Again, if difficulties arise in the levying of import duties which have
been voted by Congress, the Federal court must decide the case, because it
arises under the interpretation of a law of the United States.</p>
<p>This rule is in perfect accordance with the fundamental principles of the
Federal Constitution. The Union, as it was established in 1789, possesses,
it is true, a limited supremacy; but it was intended that within its
limits it should form one and the same people. *h Within those limits the
Union is sovereign. When this point is established and admitted, the
inference is easy; for if it be acknowledged that the United States
constitute one and the same people within the bounds prescribed by their
Constitution, it is impossible to refuse them the rights which belong to
other nations. But it has been allowed, from the origin of society, that
every nation has the right of deciding by its own courts those questions
which concern the execution of its own laws. To this it is answered that
the Union is in so singular a position that in relation to some matters it
constitutes a people, and that in relation to all the rest it is a
nonentity. But the inference to be drawn is, that in the laws relating to
these matters the Union possesses all the rights of absolute sovereignty.
The difficulty is to know what these matters are; and when once it is
resolved (and we have shown how it was resolved, in speaking of the means
of determining the jurisdiction of the Federal courts) no further doubt
can arise; for as soon as it is established that a suit is Federal—that
is to say, that it belongs to the share of sovereignty reserved by the
Constitution of the Union—the natural consequence is that it should
come within the jurisdiction of a Federal court.</p>
<p class="foot">
h <br/> [ This principle was in some measure restricted by the
introduction of the several States as independent powers into the Senate,
and by allowing them to vote separately in the House of Representatives
when the President is elected by that body. But these are exceptions, and
the contrary principle is the rule.]</p>
<p>Whenever the laws of the United States are attacked, or whenever they are
resorted to in self-defence, the Federal courts must be appealed to. Thus
the jurisdiction of the tribunals of the Union extends and narrows its
limits exactly in the same ratio as the sovereignty of the Union augments
or decreases. We have shown that the principal aim of the legislators of
1789 was to divide the sovereign authority into two parts. In the one they
placed the control of all the general interests of the Union, in the other
the control of the special interests of its component States. Their chief
solicitude was to arm the Federal Government with sufficient power to
enable it to resist, within its sphere, the encroachments of the several
States. As for these communities, the principle of independence within
certain limits of their own was adopted in their behalf; and they were
concealed from the inspection, and protected from the control, of the
central Government. In speaking of the division of authority, I observed
that this latter principle had not always been held sacred, since the
States are prevented from passing certain laws which apparently belong to
their own particular sphere of interest. When a State of the Union passes
a law of this kind, the citizens who are injured by its execution can
appeal to the Federal courts.</p>
<p>Thus the jurisdiction of the Federal courts extends not only to all the
cases which arise under the laws of the Union, but also to those which
arise under laws made by the several States in opposition to the
Constitution. The States are prohibited from making ex post facto laws in
criminal cases, and any person condemned by virtue of a law of this kind
can appeal to the judicial power of the Union. The States are likewise
prohibited from making laws which may have a tendency to impair the
obligations of contracts. *i If a citizen thinks that an obligation of
this kind is impaired by a law passed in his State, he may refuse to obey
it, and may appeal to the Federal courts. *j</p>
<p class="foot">
i <br/> [ It is perfectly clear, says Mr. Story ("Commentaries," p. 503,
or in the large edition Section 1379), that any law which enlarges,
abridges, or in any manner changes the intention of the parties, resulting
from the stipulations in the contract, necessarily impairs it. He gives in
the same place a very long and careful definition of what is understood by
a contract in Federal jurisprudence. A grant made by the State to a
private individual, and accepted by him, is a contract, and cannot be
revoked by any future law. A charter granted by the State to a company is
a contract, and equally binding to the State as to the grantee. The clause
of the Constitution here referred to insures, therefore, the existence of
a great part of acquired rights, but not of all. Property may legally be
held, though it may not have passed into the possessor's hands by means of
a contract; and its possession is an acquired right, not guaranteed by the
Federal Constitution.]</p>
<p class="foot">
j <br/> [ A remarkable instance of this is given by Mr. Story (p. 508, or
in the large edition Section 1388): "Dartmouth College in New Hampshire
had been founded by a charter granted to certain individuals before the
American Revolution, and its trustees formed a corporation under this
charter. The legislature of New Hampshire had, without the consent of this
corporation, passed an act changing the organization of the original
provincial charter of the college, and transferring all the rights,
privileges, and franchises from the old charter trustees to new trustees
appointed under the act. The constitutionality of the act was contested,
and, after solemn arguments, it was deliberately held by the Supreme Court
that the provincial charter was a contract within the meaning of the
Constitution (Art. I. Section 10), and that the emendatory act was utterly
void, as impairing the obligation of that charter. The college was deemed,
like other colleges of private foundation, to be a private eleemosynary
institution, endowed by its charter with a capacity to take property
unconnected with the Government. Its funds were bestowed upon the faith of
the charter, and those funds consisted entirely of private donations. It
is true that the uses were in some sense public, that is, for the general
benefit, and not for the mere benefit of the corporators; but this did not
make the corporation a public corporation. It was a private institution
for general charity. It was not distinguishable in principle from a
private donation, vested in private trustees, for a public charity, or for
a particular purpose of beneficence. And the State itself, if it had
bestowed funds upon a charity of the same nature, could not resume those
funds."]</p>
<p>This provision appears to me to be the most serious attack upon the
independence of the States. The rights awarded to the Federal Government
for purposes of obvious national importance are definite and easily
comprehensible; but those with which this last clause invests it are not
either clearly appreciable or accurately defined. For there are vast
numbers of political laws which influence the existence of obligations of
contracts, which may thus furnish an easy pretext for the aggressions of
the central authority.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />